Overblown: How Politicians and the Terrorism Industry Inflate National Security Threats, and Why We Believe Them (2006)

International Relations professor John Mueller wrote in this important book (and here is his 2025 paper, Military Policy Toward China: The Case Against Overreaction):

* The number of people worldwide who die as a result of international terrorism is generally a few hundred a year, tiny compared to the numbers who die in most civil wars or from automobile accidents. In fact, until 2001 far fewer Americans were killed in any grouping of years by all forms of international terrorism than were killed by lightning. And except for 2001, virtually none of these terrorist deaths occurred within the United States itself. Indeed, outside of 2001, fewer people have been killed in America by international terrorism than have drowned in toilets or have died from bee stings.Even with the September 11 attacks included in the count, however, the number of Americans killed by international terrorism since the late 1960s (which is when the State Department began its accounting) is about the same as the number killed over the same period by lightning, or by accident-causing deer, or by severe allergic reactions to peanuts. In almost all years the total number of people worldwide who die at the hands of international terrorists is not much more than the number who drown in bathtubs in the United States.

* There is little evidence that terrorists have made much, if any, progress in obtaining any kind of weapon of mass destruction, no matter how defined. However, the continual obsession about WMD has had the perverse effect of recommending at least some of them to the terrorists: as Ayman al-Zawahiri, Osama bin Laden’s right-hand man, said of biological weapons, “We only became aware of them when the enemy drew our attention to them by repeatedly expressing concerns that they can be produced simply with easily available materials.” Servicing this interest, a number of Pakistani scientists once apparently had wide-ranging—if, according to them, “academic”—discussions with bin Laden concerning nuclear, chemical, and biological weapons. Conceivably, these talks might eventually have led to something more extensive, but contacts were severed after, and because of, the events of 9/11.34 In the meantime, al-Qaeda’s scientific capacities seem to be very limited indeed.

* The chief costs of terrorism derive not from the damage inflicted by the terrorists, but what those attacked do to themselves and others in response. That is, the harm of terrorism mostly arises from the fear and from the often hasty, ill-considered, and overwrought reaction (or overreaction) it characteristically, and often calculatedly, inspires in its victims.

* To begin with, the reaction to 9/11 has claimed more—far more—human lives than were lost in the terrorist attacks. Some of this derived from the fears that the terrorists inspired. Many people canceled airline trips and consequently traveled more by automobile after the event, and one study has concluded that more than 1,000 people died in automobile accidents in 2001 alone between September 11 and December 31 because of such evasive behavior. If a small percentage of the hundreds of thousands of road deaths suffered after 2001 occurred to people who were driving because they feared to fly, the number of Americans who have perished in overreaction to 9/11 in automobile accidents alone could well surpass the number who were killed by the terrorists on that terrible day.

Moreover, the reaction to 9/11 included two wars that are yet ongoing—one in Afghanistan, the other in Iraq—neither of which would have been politically possible without 9/11. The number of Americans, civilian and military, who have died thus far in those ventures surpasses the number killed on September 11. Moreover, the best estimates are that the war in Iraq has resulted in the deaths of tens of thousands of Iraqis, with one analysis suggesting that 100,000 Iraqis perished during the war’s first eighteen months alone. This could represent more fatalities than were inflicted by all terrorism, domestic and international, during the entire twentieth century.

The mental health costs stemming from the fear and anxiety induced by the 9/11 attacks are also likely to be extensive. A notable, but probably extreme, example of how severe these can be comes from extensive studies of the health effect of the Chernobyl nuclear disaster in the Soviet Union in 1986. It has been found that the largest health consequences came not from the accident itself (fewer than fifty people died directly from radiation exposure), but from the negative and often life-expectancy-reducing impact on the mental health of people traumatized by relocation and by lingering, and greatly exaggerated, fears that they would soon die of cancer. In the end, such lifestyle afflictions as alcoholism, drug abuse, chronic anxiety, and fatalism have posed a much greater threat to health, and essentially have killed far more people, than exposure to Chernobyl’s radiation. The mental health impact of 9/11 is unlikely to prove to be as extensive, but one study found that 17 percent of the American population outside of New York City was still reporting symptoms of September 11–related posttraumatic stress two months after the attacks.

The economic costs of the reaction to 9/11 are also high. Although the direct economic losses imposed by the terrorists, amounting to tens of billions of dollars, were spectacular, the economic cost of the reaction runs several times that.

* The yearly budget for the Department of Homeland Security is approaching $50 billion per year, and state and local governments spend additional billions. The United States now expends fully $4 billion a year on airline passenger screenings alone, and another $4.7 billion on zapping checked baggage; the air marshal program, massively expanded after 9/11, costs over half a billion more. Safety measures carry additional consequences: one economist calculates that strictures effectively requiring people to spend an additional half-hour in airports cost the economy $15 billion per year, another puts it at $8 billion. (By comparison, total airline profits in the 1990s never exceeded $5.5 billion per year.) Longer airport waits also harm the airlines by reducing short-haul passenger traffic, and they can cost lives by encouraging people to travel more by automobile. The reaction to the anthrax letters of 2001 will cost the U.S. Post Office alone some $5 billion—that is, $1 billion for every fatality inflicted by the terrorist. Various 9/11-induced restrictions on visas have constricted visits and residencies of scientists, engineers, and businesspeople vital to the economy, restrictions that, some predict, will dampen American economic growth in a few years. Universities are deeply concerned because they depend heavily on foreign graduate students, particularly in the sciences, and student visa applications fell some 21 percent from 2001 to 2004 while the number of graduate school applications from abroad fell by 21 percent between 2004 and 2005. The Joint Economic Committee of the U.S. Congress anticipates that economic growth will be lowered because of increased spending on security. In 2006, when oil was selling for $70 a barrel, market experts estimated that $7 to $10 of that price was due to fears of another terrorist attack in the United States.

Then there are the economic costs of the terrorism-induced wars in Afghanistan and Iraq. In the case of Iraq alone, these are likely to run to a monumental $1 trillion to $2 trillion.

In addition, there have been great opportunity costs: the enormous sums of money being spent to deal with this presumed threat have in part been diverted from other, possibly more worthy endeavors. Some of the money doubtless would have been spent on similar ventures under earlier budgets, and much of it likely has wider benefits than simply securing the country against the rather limited threat of terrorism. But much of it has very likely been pulled away from programs that do much good—programs devoted to housing, health, and education, for example.

Thus, the country’s obsessive focus on terrorism after 9/11 has resulted in severe funding distortions. For example, after 2001 the government spent extravagantly and wastefully on a perishable (and, as it happened, utterly unnecessary) anthrax vaccine while letting itself become undersupplied with influenza vaccine. In 2005, 758 scientists, including two Nobel Prize winners, raised an outcry because of what they saw as a major shift of research funds from pathogens of high public health significance to obscure organisms of high biodefense, but low public health, importance. Almost 75 percent of the appropriations for first responders went for terrorism rather than for natural disasters; and $2 billion was made available in grants to improve preparedness for terrorism but only $180 million for natural disasters, something that may have contributed to inept governmental measures to deal with the results of Hurricane Katrina in 2005. The budget for the FBI has been increased since 9/11, but not enough to pay for all the terrorism work it is now required to do. Funds have had to be shifted from its other programs, such as fighting crime: after 9/11, in fact, fully 67 percent of those working on criminal investigations were reassigned to the counterterrorism beat. A rise in the rate of violent crime in 2005 has been attributed by some police chiefs in part to the pressure on local cops to divert resources and personnel to homeland security endeavors.

The costs of reaction are also extensive in other ways, many of them unmeasurable. For example, the park at City Hall in Manhattan was extensively and successfully refurbished in 2000. After September 11, 2001, major portions were chained shut in fear of terrorists, and ordinary citizens can now experience its beauties only by peering at it through a fence.

As two analysts put it, the country’s priorities have become “radically torqued” toward homeland defense and fighting terrorism while other important societal needs go underaddressed. For example, one observer has suggested that if a small portion of the excessive spending on airline security had been spent instead on enforcing automobile seat belt laws, the number of lives saved would likely have been considerable. This process is especially unfortunate because, as risk analyst David Banks puts it, if resources are directed away from sensible programs and future growth to pursue “unachievable but politically popular levels of domestic security,” the terrorists have won “an important victory that mortgages our future.”

Posted in China | Comments Off on Overblown: How Politicians and the Terrorism Industry Inflate National Security Threats, and Why We Believe Them (2006)

Creating Space

I moved with my parents from Cooranbong, Australia, to California’s Napa Valley in May of 1977. I was 11. I wasn’t good at making friends, so I spent my time reading books and dreaming about how awesome I would be when I got my freedom.

My Seventh-Day Adventist preacher daddy had fans and one of them gave us some radios, one of which I took. I had never owned a radio before. I now had a pipeline to the exciting low-brow world of sports and pop music.

We didn’t have a TV, so my radio was my most exciting companion. It showed a universe to me where I could be great. I could be the next Brent Musburger or Dan Rather or Howard Cosell.

I played sports but I wasn’t any good. I wasn’t the worst. I was just average. I last played on a team at age 18 when I was living in Tannum Sands, Australia, after graduating from high school in California. I was part of the BITS (Boyne Island Tannum Sands) soccer club. I played on the B team without distinction. I had no special talent, but I showed up to practice regularly and did what I was told.

After age 18, sports became something that I watched.

I love a good fight. Sports rehearse you for life’s battles. Watching wasn’t just escape—it felt like training.

Life is a team sport. Group strategy will usually out-compete individual strategy — both for happiness and for effectiveness. Walking a mile or two on your own without distractions can be a chore, but walking five miles with a friend is a joy.

From age 22 on, I struggled with exhaustion (due to my vegetarian diet I found out at age 55). I came to welcome anything that gave me a clean burst of pep.

As someone prone to emotional addictions (by 2015, I was in five 12-step programs for various process addictions), however, I knew that cheap excitement is dangerous for me.

During the last World Cup, I read half a dozen books on soccer and earned the right to watch soccer intelligently.

Soccer strategy revolves around creating space while on offense and reducing space for the opponent when you are on defense. Possession is king.

This resonated with me. Like most blokes, I like freedom and space. The more possibilities, the better (until there are too many, when they become exhausting). If I don’t take action, life hems me in. Like Dirk Diggler, I see myself as a big bright shining star, and I don’t want to be henpecked.

When I misread myself and the world, my attempts at freedom often backfire and shrink my life. For example, by creating space for myself by speaking freely, I sometimes hacked away at my most important relationships, and in the loneliness that resulted, I felt miserable (on the other hand, appropriate bravery when wisely speaking up helped me to connect with others, particularly online). Chasing freedom through self-employment often shrank my life into financial desperation. Once I accepted a normal job, my money problems diminished and I felt freer. I perform better at work when I feel like a star, but I have to demonstrate to those around me that I am in on the joke lest they hate me.

A subterranean motive driving my conversion to Judaism was my overwhelming conviction by age 22 that left to my own devices, I would destroy myself and damage those around me. I knew I needed less space, and less freedom to choose. As I moved into Judaism, however, the closeness often felt like it was strangling me (it’s hard to convert to a ritualistic religion from a non-ritualized background), and the fallout hurt both me and others.

As I moved into my forties, I felt gratitude for the balance that Orthodox Judaism offered me between individualism and group identity. For example, pretty much anything I want to talk about, I can find an Orthodox Jew or two to have that chinwag, but I should always take care not to say things to unnecessarily hurt those around. I’m not as bonded with the tribe as your normal Orthodox Jew, after all I’m a bachelor, but I am more bonded to the group than I would be if I only followed my inclinations. These days I’m better able to choose the right amount of freedom and connection for myself and for those affected by me. For example, I can volunteer up to ten hours a week without feeling stifled, but if I consistently volunteer over 15 hours of week, I burn out and want to run away from my commitments.

When I expand wisely, I’m playing offense; when I set boundaries, I’m on defense. The trick is not to forget that both are part of the same game.

When I join groups, there’s a part of me that wants to show I know better than everyone else in the group and therefore I should be the leader. This path leads to my destruction. My drive for distinction over connection (I bet many of us mistake the craving to stand out for a path to freedom, when in fact it can cut us off from the very people who make freedom possible) is not a winning formula, but I can’t kill it. I can only follow God or 12-Steps or Good Orderly Direction that push me towards more connection than is natural for me. What is natural for me is not optimal for me.

I still love enormous amounts of solitude to read and to write, but when that isolation slips into loneliness, I drown it in Dallas Cowboys highlights on YouTube.

When I watch Dak Prescott throw a touchdown pass, or I watch Brad Pitt drive a race car in the F1 movie, I experience it as though it’s me doing the cool things.

Do normal people watch movies without feeling part of the story?

ChatGPT says:

Here’s why some people immerse much more deeply than others when watching sports or movies:

1. Absorption & Imagination

Psychologists talk about a trait called absorption—the ability to become fully immersed in an activity or story. People high in absorption often lose themselves in music, books, or movies. They blur the line between imagination and reality more vividly.

2. Mirror Neurons

Neuroscience shows that when you watch someone perform an action—like Dak Prescott throwing a pass—your brain activates some of the same neural pathways as if you were doing it yourself. For some people, this mirroring is stronger, making the vicarious experience more real.

3. Personality Factors

Openness to experience: People who are curious, imaginative, and emotionally sensitive often immerse more deeply.

Empathy: If you’re naturally tuned into others’ emotions, you may step more easily into a character’s shoes.

Sensation-seeking: If you crave intensity, you might “lean into” movies or sports to get that rush as if it were happening to you.

4. Life History

If you once played sports (even without distinction), your body remembers. Watching can light up those same motor memories, so the game feels like your game.

If you dreamed of broadcasting, racing, or stardom, movies scratch that itch—your identity hooks into the story.

5. State of Mind

Fatigue, stress, or longing for escape can make people more prone to “merge” with what they watch. That’s why someone burned out might binge action movies and feel like they’ve lived an adventure.

6. Cultural Framing

We’re trained to see sports and movies as participatory. Cheering, chanting, crying—those are signals that you’re meant to join in, not stay detached.

So: normal people do feel part of the story, but not everyone to the same degree. Some watch a touchdown like they’re on the field. Others just notice the stats.

When I get clarity, I feel exhilarated. I expand. When I feel bad, when I’m defeated and humiliated by life, I feel oppressed and small. My choices diminish. One great thing psychotherapy gave me was a realization that I always had more options than I initially believed. After failure, part of me wants to collapse and give up and crawl into a cave and say there’s no point trying.

Alexander Technique, therapy, 12-step work, volunteering, and beef organ capsules are the greatest things I’ve done over the past 20 years to create more space for myself while staying connected to those I love.

At 59, I’m still playing the same game I played at 18 — knowing when to spread the field and when to close it down.

I asked ChatGPT: What other areas of life can be understood this way of creating and closing space? Where else might these strategies apply outside of sports?

ChatGPT said:

Some parallels:

Negotiation and Business

Offense: you create space by broadening options, introducing new terms, or reframing issues so you have more room to maneuver.

Defense: you restrict space by narrowing the scope, limiting concessions, and controlling the terms of discussion.

Conversation and Debate

Offense: ask open-ended questions, invite perspectives, and give people room to express themselves.

Defense: tighten the focus, push back on digressions, and constrain the range of acceptable arguments.

Creativity and Problem-Solving

Offense: deliberately expand the space of ideas—brainstorm widely, consider far-out options, let thoughts flow without judgment.

Defense: later restrict the field—apply criteria, eliminate weak options, narrow down to the feasible.

Parenting or Teaching

Offense: give kids room to explore, make mistakes, and find their own way.

Defense: set boundaries, keep them safe, and block harmful paths.

Politics and Law

Offense: create space through broad coalitions, new legislation, or expanding rights.

Defense: restrict space through regulation, precedent, or narrowing interpretation.

Personal Boundaries

Offense: open yourself to new relationships, opportunities, or experiences.

Defense: close off toxic dynamics, set firm limits, and protect your time and energy.

Have Republicans under Trump opened space for their team and restricted space for their enemies? Are Democrats fighting back by opening space and restricting space for their enemies?

ChatGPT said:

Both sides constantly work the “space” game, just in different directions.

Republicans under Trump (opening space):

Expanded the rhetorical and cultural space for openly nationalist, anti-establishment, and grievance-driven politics. Things that once felt “off-limits” in mainstream discourse became normalized.

Opened space in the judiciary and regulatory arenas by prioritizing deregulation, reducing oversight, and seating conservative judges who reinterpret the law in ways that give more leeway to business, religion, and gun rights.

Republicans under Trump (restricting space):

Restricted access to immigration, voting, reproductive rights, and federal agency expertise (e.g., science-based policymaking).

Worked to narrow the acceptable range of history and school curricula (culture-war battles over “woke” content, DEI, etc.).

Democrats (opening space):

Expanded conversations about equity, diversity, climate change, and healthcare.

Pushed voting rights legislation, student debt relief efforts, and new space for environmental regulation and clean energy investment.

Opened rhetorical space for marginalized groups (LGBTQ+, racial justice, immigrant rights).

Democrats (restricting space):

Tried to restrict corporate influence, monopolistic practices, and the power of fossil fuels.

Imposed or defended regulations in healthcare, environment, workplace protections.

Pushed back against Trump-aligned efforts by restricting space for disinformation (social media regulation attempts, legal challenges to election lies).

In short: each party plays offense by expanding certain freedoms or conversations that serve its coalition, and plays defense by narrowing or constraining freedoms that empower the other side.

Here’s how the “space” lens works in art and technology:

Art

Offense (creating space):

Artists break conventions, invent new forms, and expand the field of what counts as art. Impressionism, abstract expressionism, performance art—all were about pushing boundaries to open new creative space.

Within a single work, artists create space for ambiguity, interpretation, and emotional range so viewers can bring themselves into the piece.

Defense (restricting space):

Critics, curators, and institutions often narrow the field by deciding which works or styles are “serious,” canonical, or fundable.

Artists themselves sometimes choose restraint—minimalism, limited palettes, or strict forms—as a way to heighten meaning by constraining possibility.

Technology

Offense (creating space):

Innovators open new arenas of possibility: the internet created vast new spaces for communication and commerce; AI expands space for automation and creative tools.

Open-source movements deliberately create space for collective development and experimentation.

Defense (restricting space):

Companies restrict space by walling off ecosystems (Apple’s App Store rules, proprietary platforms).

Governments and ethicists restrict space with regulation (data privacy laws, limits on surveillance tech).

Even within design, restriction can be a feature—good UX often reduces user choice to simplify, focus, and prevent error.

So in both art and tech, there’s a constant dance: bold expansion that makes new worlds possible, followed by selective narrowing to refine, protect, or control.

Here’s a unifying framework you can carry across domains:

The Law of Space Management

Life is a game of managing space—when to expand it and when to contract it.

Creating Space (Offense)

Expand options, choices, and opportunities.

Increase freedom of movement, thought, or action.

Encourage diversity, experimentation, and possibility.

Risk: too much space can lead to chaos, overwhelm, or lack of focus.

Restricting Space (Defense)

Narrow choices to sharpen focus and efficiency.

Set boundaries that protect people, values, or resources.

Eliminate noise, distractions, or threats.

Risk: too much restriction leads to stagnation, rigidity, or oppression.

The Dynamic Balance

Success in any domain depends on the rhythm between expansion and contraction.

Innovation comes from expanding the field, then narrowing to what works.

Relationships thrive when space is given for growth but bounded by respect.

Politics swings between periods of opening rights and tightening order.

Art flourishes when bold experimentation is later refined into form.

General Rule

Expand when you need possibility.

Contract when you need clarity.

Mastery comes from knowing when to do which.

The Law of Space Management

Life is a game of managing space—when to expand it and when to contract it.

1. Creating Space (Offense)

Open possibilities, invite movement, multiply options.

Encourage exploration, experimentation, and freedom.

Broaden horizons by reframing, innovating, and disrupting norms.

Use when: you need growth, fresh energy, or new solutions.

Risk: too much space creates noise, overwhelm, or drift.

2. Restricting Space (Defense)

Narrow choices, sharpen focus, protect boundaries.

Cut distractions, eliminate weak options, define limits.

Constrain to clarify, protect, and enforce order.

Use when: you need clarity, discipline, or security.

Risk: too much restriction leads to rigidity, stagnation, or repression.

3. The Rhythm

Expansion and contraction must alternate.

Innovation = expand wildly, then contract sharply.

Relationships = give room to grow, but anchor with respect.

Politics = rights expand, then order reigns them in.

Art = exploration followed by form.

Technology = new tools create space, regulation and design contract it.

4. The Master Principle

Expand when you need possibility.

Contract when you need clarity.

Mastery is knowing which moment demands which.

Posted in Personal | Comments Off on Creating Space

How To Tap Expertise For Fun & Profit!

Had the U.S. achieved Australia’s cumulative COVID death rate through 2023, something like 700,000–1,000,000 American lives could have been saved.

ChatGPT organized my thoughts:

1) Core stance

  1. Asymmetric risk rule: When stakes are high and the downside is catastrophic (death, long COVID, health-system collapse), bias toward precautionary measures backed by mainstream public-health evidence; relax quickly as evidence permits.
  2. Performance over vibes: Prefer claims that show output legitimacy—they work in practice, not just in journals.
  3. Institutional realism: Expertise is powerful but partial; treat it as a tool embedded in funding, incentives, and consensus machinery, not an oracle. See Turner’s The Politics of Expertise and Liberal Democracy 3.0.

2) What counts as “settled enough”

  • Converging evidence: Mechanism + high-quality studies + real-world outcomes align.
  • Replication or durable performance: Results hold up outside the lab.
  • Transparent consensus: Commission/consensus statements publish methods, assumptions, and any minority views.
  • Scope discipline: Experts flag when they leave “is” for “ought.”

3) Turner’s system critique (why experts can be right and wrong)

Modern knowledge production is a superb consensus machine built around grants, peer competition, and patent races. It rewards narrow, fundable interventions and sidelines comprehensive understanding. See Turner’s essay “Expertise in Crisis.”

4) New filter: Intervention vs. Understanding

  • Intervention-science (what the system funds): fast, focused, scalable solutions (e.g., vaccines). The system executed brilliantly here.
  • Understanding-science (what the system underfunds): integrated, long-horizon insight (transmission in context, heterogeneity, long-term sequelae). Expect gaps unless explicitly funded and organized.

5) Paul’s lens: don’t confuse elite signals with truth

Elite institutions can rapidly reset moral frames and police discourse. Treat elite consensus as a social signal, not evidence; always demand the data. See Darel E. Paul’s From Tolerance to Equality.

6) COVID application

  • Vaccines: A genuine success of intervention-science; lifesaving and central to exit from acute crisis.
  • Against revisionism: The “let it rip” / herd-immunity gambit was a harmful overcorrection that failed empirically and ethically; see Howard’s We Want Them Infected and scholarly review here.
  • Policy communication: Separate “what we know,” “what we infer,” and “what we value;” publish decision trails and sunset/review points.

7) Acceptance checklist (use before taking a stand)

  1. Competence check: Is the expert speaking within their training, or making political/ethical tradeoffs?
  2. Evidence maturity: Multiple independent lines, replication, and external validity?
  3. Process quality: Transparent consensus with visible dissent and COI disclosures?
  4. Incentive stress-test: Are grantsmanship, patents, or prestige messaging outrunning the data?
  5. Elite-signal filter: Would you still accept this claim if it came from a low-status venue with identical evidence?
  6. Intervention vs. understanding: Is this a narrow fix or a comprehensive account? Adjust confidence accordingly.

8) Action rules in a crisis

  • Lower-regret path: Prefer measures that reduce worst-case outcomes (vaccination, ventilation, targeted NPIs), then step down as metrics improve.
  • Sunset and review: Every extraordinary measure has an expiry date, predefined rollback metrics (hospital load, excess mortality, vax coverage), and periodic public review.
  • Equity check: Anticipate unequal burdens; build mitigations in from day one.

9) Red lines

  • Strategies that foreseeably increase preventable harm (e.g., deliberate mass infection) fail the asymmetric-risk rule; exclude unless facts materially change and survive independent review. See Howard.

10) Update rule (pivot without whiplash)

  • Predeclare the metrics that will trigger changes.
  • When pivoting, state what evidence shifted, why prior guidance was reasonable at the time, and what you expect next.

11) How to write with this model

  1. Start with the harm baseline (what if we do nothing?).
  2. Place today’s claim on the evidence maturity ladder.
  3. Run the competence/process/incentive/elite checks and the intervention vs. understanding filter.
  4. State the action with sunset + metrics and list uncertainties + what would change your mind.

Key references

Posted in Expertise | Comments Off on How To Tap Expertise For Fun & Profit!

Stewards Of Democracy: Law As Public Profession (1999)

Law professor Paul D. Carrington wrote:

The concept of a “liberal” krytocracy [rule by judges] — one fired by a desire to transform the social order it governs — may have unique at the time of its advent in post-World War II, post-Brown America.

Perhaps the leading twentieth-century practitioner of constitutional law-making in disregard of the rights of citizens to govern themselves was William Brennan… [T]he inflated sense of the Court’s role he seems to be have brought to its work helped to make the Court to resemble a College of Cardinals telling members of the faith what to believe and how to live. The Brennan “encyclicals” required the community to respect a broad range of individual and minority rights, and left little discretion to local congregations or constituencies to believe, or to act upon the belief, that somewhat more communitarianism and less individualism or pluralism might be preferable. The encyclicals were not presented as serious interpretations of a written legal text, but were rooted in natural law sanctioned by reference to the indeterminate text of the Fourteenth Amendment and to what Justice Brennan presumed to be the better instincts and ideals of the people. He was fairly said to be a non-interpretivist engaged in “a search for political-moral knowledge, for answers to the various questions as to how we, the polity, should live our public, collective life, or life in common” and sometimes our not so public life, too. Unlike Cooley or Brandeis, Brennan seldom if ever gave weight to the political judgment of elected officers, perhaps especially those elected at state or local levels. Frankfurter only somewhat unjustly described the Brennan Court as animated by “self-willed, self-righteous power lust.” Whether lustful or not, the Court embraced the belief that anything a legislature could do, it could do better.

There is irony in the denotation of this anti-democratic restoration of judicial supremacy as “liberal,” a sort of code word for the moral preferences of the recently emerged “national class.” As Christopher Lasch explained the irony, many ruling meritocrats revolted against the moral values of those less-esteemed persons who merely vote, pay taxes, bear and raise the Republic’s children, and put themselves at risk in its defense. A visible means of avoiding the noisome duty of persuading these lesser persons of the correct world view was to constitutionalize political issues that would otherwise be subjects of popular governance. The meritocracy in revolt may, if Lasch is correct, have supplied the receptive audience needed to induce high court judges to discard the caution advocated by earlier “liberals” favoring the right to self-government. Indeed, Frankfurter despised that his colleagues were determined to be immortalized in “the Valhalla of liberty” and “in the meantime to have the avant-gard of the Yale Law School…praise them.”

A different interpretation is that of Michael Sandel, who blames the Supreme Court for displacing the earlier American tradition of shared power with a new vision of “freedom” elevating individual autonomy and governmental neutrality at the expense of the bonds uniting us in a common venture. men venture. Evidence to support his hypothesis can be found not only in the conduct of the Court, but also in legal scholarship disregarding the possibility that life-tenured judges ought to or could be influenced in the formulation of doctrine by “the common thoughts of men” or other communitarian concerns, expressing wonder that anyone should be concerned about the Court’s “anti-majoritarianism” and dismissing the concern as platitudinous.

Whatever the social-psychological origins of this anti-democratic “liberalism,” it called into question the validity and integrity of the traditional political rhetoric of the Republic. Life-tenured judges are not in any useful sense “we, the people,” however much one might wish to believe otherwise. To speak of krytocracy as a government of or by the people is a transparent fraud on citizens’ political rights. While none can deny, as Justice Robert Jackson affirmed, that the “very purpose” of constitutions is
“to withdraw certain subjects from the vicissitudes of political controversy,” when “certain subjects” include many or most of those of greatest interest to citizens, the effect, as he noted, is to withdraw the life-giving oxygen from the air sustaining self-government.

As we have seen, our exemplars were mindful of at least three grave problems inherent in political rule by judges. First, as Cooley’s message at Harvard reflected, they believed that a judiciary disregarding the “common thoughts of men” will be resisted by those whose thoughts it disdains. In this view, people do not change their minds, and often not even their behavior, because of the utterances of senior citizens in black robes, especially if they are imbued with the individualist spirit of Protestantism. Judgments of high courts purporting to effect social change are therefore often useless and sometimes counterproductive. On the other hand, Cooley and his successors supposed that people will more readily adapt to policies debated and decided by democratic methods in which they participated, especially if their dissenting views have been prudently accommodated. Second, my exemplars recognized that judges as a class are not selected for their political and moral wisdom, nor is there reason or experience to suggest that they acquire it in office. “Wayward” as Hand observed the vagaries of popular assemblies” to be, judges of all political persuasions are capable of equally colossal political blunders. There are at least three reasons for this. One is that the judicial process is not well suited to the presentation and assimilation of political wisdom. The Brandeis brief to the contrary notwithstanding, legislatures and administrative rulemakers are, as Freund observed, structurally more adept at “mastering statistics and economics,” as Holmes prescribed, because they have direct access to technical expertise as well as to popular estimates of such expertise and have no obligation to address an imminent dispute when they have well-founded doubt about the right solution. A second reason, as Freund emphasized, is that the judiciary can seldom broker prudent compromise between competing values, and compromise is more often than not the wisest policy. That “the best is the enemy of the good” is an adverse comment on much judicial policymaking. A third reason is that the doctrine of precedent to which American courts are necessarily committed dictates that they cannot readily correct their policymaking mistakes. Having written, the judicial hand moves on. For all these reasons, political blunders by the judiciary may be more likely and more costly, even though they are more likely to bear the marks of principled decisionmaking…

The efforts of judges to transform the social order without the general moral support of the citizens are not very effective and are often counterproductive…

After Brown, it seemed that every beleaguered individual group in America, including perhaps some beleaguered only in their own perceptions, fancied that the court in its anti-democratic role might relieve their distress. The idea of popular sovereignty came to be viewed by many American lawyers…as a mere impediment to social reform. And the role of the federal judiciary became once again redolent of the overbearing and pretentious role of the chancellor wielding power in the name of the king’s conscience…

While Brown stands as the shining example of the good deeds that politically animated, life-tenured judges may on occasion perform when their decisions are congruent with widely shared moral precepts, even the Court’s performance with respect to racial segregation is mixed and can be said at times to manifest misuse of its political power. When the Court at last ordered lower federal courts to reorganize and manage the public schools, and not merely in the South where segregation was de jure, it pitted its authority broadly against self-government in communities spread across the continent…

The spirit of Southern rednecks who wanted to impeach Earl Warren was nationalized in the politics of George Wallace, the angry governor of Alabama, who by denouncing the “pointy-headed intellectuals” marshaled a huge vote in the 1968 Democratic primaries in northern states. Many individual federal judges were subject to strenuous efforts to intimidate them; numerous Michigan bumper stickers called not for the impeachment, but the assassination, of Judge Stephen Roth for ordering bussed integration of all the schools in metropolitan Detroit, one of many cities in which school populations reflected segregated housing patterns caused in minor part by historic misuses of local political power reflecting racist impulses. That extremely hostile reaction was most visible in the westside suburbs, which were populated by the offspring of twentieth-century immigrants from eastern Europe who bore no responsibility for historic harms and who perceived no reason why their children should bear the burden and inconvenience of desegregating African-American children for sins they did not commit. Judge Roth, himself an immigrant, was likely responding in his order to the evidence that the burden of desegregation, if limited to the city of Detroit, would fall entirely on those least responsible for it and leave free of any inconvenience the monied, “national” class residing in Grosse Pointe and Bloomfield Hills. While an appeal from his order was pending, he died of a heart attack, quite possibly caused by the stress associated with the odium attached to his decision.

The effect outside the South was to uproot neighborhood schools in black neighborhoods as well as white. Sacrificed in the effort to promote racial integration was the traditional relationship between public education and the family. Derrick Bell, made the point that it was not merely white parents, but also black, whose responsibility and authority over the education of their children was diminished. There is even reason to suspect that the psychological justifications for desegregation were harmfully
self-fulfilling, perhaps even foreseeably so. While it would be unjust to suggest that there was a clearly superior approach to the achievement of public school desegregation or to blame the Court for the poor estate of public education in America at the century’s end, Brown II and its progeny surely made a contribution to the demise of public schools. And, over the longer term, public education as a means by which citizens share the tutelage of their children may be more vital to the Republic than the Constitution itself. On that account, the federal courts have substantially but belatedly abandoned the goal of racial integration of school children as one that is both unattainable and counterproductive. In the extensions of its application, Brown II has indeed been silently overruled.

School desegregation was the defining moment for the “liberal” Court and profession, but it was only a point of departure. With equally high purpose, the Court soon undertook by judicial decree to transform other aspects of American society. Near the top of the agenda was the transformation of state and local police…

The Court in 1964 went beyond its moral and political support in regulating police conduct. In a pivotal case, it held that the Fourteenth Amendment prohibited a state from using a confession secured by questioning conducted before the accused consulted his counsel. And, a year later, it held that the state must advise the accused of his right to counsel before questioning, else a conviction based in part on his confession must be reversed. These decisions were not well-received by those whose obedience was required, for at least three reasons. First, they appeared to require radical change in the customary practices of local police departments everywhere. Second, they coincided with a precipitous increase in violent crime in most American cities. Third, they resulted in the release of persons, many or most of whom were almost certainly guilty of serious crime…

The Court also undertook the reformation of state prisons. There can be no doubt of the squalid conditions of many of them, but whether judges run materially more humane prisons than wardens remains open to debate…

Justice Brennan in his retirement cheerfully forecast that “one day the Court will outlaw the death penalty. Permanently.” It seems never to have occurred to him that the abolition of capital punishment is properly a task for those who write and amend the constitutions and laws of the states and not for his College of Cardinals to decide without regard for citizens’ rights to self-government…

Among the most lawless of Justice Brennan’s opinions was his decision to savage by subtle means the popular institution of the right to jury trial in civil cases…

There is no principle of natural law by which the line between church and state can be judged. While justices may suppose that “the dissemination of science” is a “sufficient agent” of civic moral education to sustain a community capable of self-government, theirs is a “culture of disbelief.” The contrary belief of the Founders that religious life is needed to sustain the ties of community essential to democratic government is another that has not been falsified…

The new age of judicial heroics tracked the advent of the legal academy… Felix Frankfurter declared… “law and lawyers are what the law schools make them.” …industrialization creating Americans’ appetite for technical competence certified by academic credentials…

Since [1900], the legal academy has been drifting into the academic profession and away from the legal profession… The academic profession in America has at least since 1950 outranked the legal profession in social status, to those preoccupied with affect, the doctorate in philosophy in any discipline is a more luminous achievement than a mere law degree and license…

Academization threatens the very benefits it confers by reducing the prospect that studious authors will be taken seriously by those bearing public responsibility. If Holmes’s lightning of genius should strike a law professor today, it is unlikely that “the real world” would notice. The reasons for this are enumerated below. First, academic lawyers achieve status within their profession less by performing useful service to the Republic than by meeting conventional academic standards requiring the utterance of novel ideas pitched to a high level of abstraction. “The remoter and more general aspects of the law are those which give it universal interest,” Holmes said. In pursuing what seem to be issues of universal dimension, academicians tend to forego study of those lesser ones that they might be able to solve and on which public officers are likely to accept their counsel. The tendency to engage in cosmology, or what Linda Mullenix has denoted as “metarealism,” is likely reinforced by the increase in the number of law teachers holding doctorates in other more esteemed disciplines. Ironically, metarealism, even in the extreme form of nihilism denying the integrity of legal texts, is in post-modern diction often denoted as “pragmatism. Yet, as Charles Collier noted, there is very little legal scholarship today resembling three prosaic articles appearing together in an early issue of the Harvard Law Review: Brandeis and Warren, “The Law of Ponds”; Beale, “Tickets”; or Williston, “Successive Promises of the Same Performance.” Instead, legal scholars are prone to exhibit their mastery of almost any other discipline than law.

Second, most large legal ideas were entertained in the time of Justinian, if not even in the time of Hammurabi. There are no new continents of law to explore. Academic lawyers are in this respect in an unfortunate position not unlike that of gross anatomists, who have no hope of discovering a new organ in the human body and are therefore scorned by their medical re- search colleagues who have large mysteries to pierce and whose literature may achieve seeming miracles. This appears to be the realization expressed by Holmes when he quit academic life for the bench. Third, as Cooley remarked at Harvard, and as Cicero and Thucydides had previously observed, sound, useful legal ideas are generally conven- tional ones. So even Holmes conceded that law must respect “the habits of a particular people at a particular time.” “The life of the law is not logic, but experience,” he said in his most famous utterance. Good law expresses the culture of which it is a part and is therefore confined by the moral premises of that culture.

Ernst Freund made the point that: “It is not possible to work a [legal] system successfully if its fundamental justifi- cation is constantly questioned; or putting it the other way, a great system that has established itself will convert its disciples from skeptics into votaries, or will quickly get rid of them. Law, like other human institutions, is a working compromise, and the very fact that it is an appeal to reason demands assump- tions that must not be too closely questioned.”

This reality is odious to academicians of pure heart who regard it as their duty and their privilege to question all the premises of the social order. In this respect, there is a fundamental, but seldom noted, conflict of interest in academic law. Fourth, cloistered scholars are physically isolated from the universe in which real decisions are made. Sound moral judgment on public issues is an attribute not easily acquired within the academic cloister. To be useful advisers and critics to those exercising public responsibility, legal scholars would need to involve themselves in active politics to a degree that few do. Thus, in 1896 Woodrow Wilson, then president of Princeton University, deplored the tendency of professional academics to treat texts as “material” and “not life”; they do not, he said, reflect, so much as “they set forth schemes, [and] expound with dispassionate method.” “Their minds,” he perceived, “are not stages, but museums; nothing is done there, but very curious and valuable collections are kept there.”

Fifth, for reasons implicit in the foregoing observations, the academic enterprise encourages utopian dogmatization. It does not reward the practice of moral compromise, which…is the objective of democratic policies and law. The complex constitutional structure of the Republic was designed precisely to prevent the political implementation of dogma, to compel compromise… Utopianism in the academy has been reinforced by the tendency of the heroic judiciary to perform the role of Cardinals willing to issue decrees to effect all manner of benign results.

Sixth, public decisions…are reactive to immediacies… Even judges and lawyers sympathetic to positions taken by academics infrequently have time or energy to consult academic literature with the care required by turgid academic prose.

Seventh, academic authors are often disinclined to accept the modest role…as mere secondary authorities… To write such work [as 1883’s A Treatise on the Constitutional Limitations Which Rest upon the Legislative Power of the States of the American Union by Thomas M. Cooley], authors must eschew novel thoughts and to that extent disavow not only academic status seeking but the more immediate satisfactions of self-expression…

Eighth, work on intellectual frontiers…often employs the professional jargon of another academic discipline, a jargon likely to impede, if it does not prevent, comprehension by judges and practicing lawyers… The university law school is increasingly a colonial outpost of the graduate school. A self-respecting law school serving the “national class” would be ashamed not to have on its faculty a broad sampling of scholars whose in- terests in law is incidental to a primary intellectual interest in another more academically respectable field, an interest certified by a doctorate in that field. Their work is often difficult to communicate effectively to persons outside the pertinent intellectual community.

Ninth, academic status is seldom acquired by work on the law and politics of local institutions. For the most respected academic lawyers, only the federal government or the international order is worthy of study. Work of the sort done by Freund with state and local governments is out of fashion because it does not command the attention and admiration of the “national class.”

These enumerated circumstances have an aspect of self-fulfilling proph- ecy. Teachers and writers who do not expect a hearing from those in power and not to invest themselves in the effort to address the nonexistent audience in ways that would be helpful to it. As a consequence, …much that now passes for scholarship by law professors is not written with an expectation that it might be read and used by those having public responsibility, with whom academic authors find little or no common ground. It is often discourse addressed to small audiences of specialized academic readers having little involvement in the immediate cares of the world. Academic lawyers therefore frequently achieve the fate of being ignored by those whom they ignore. Indeed, it may be questioned whether many legal academics are still lawyers or instead have become political philosophers. As such, they may be subject to the complaint made against some of the most eminent members of that esteemed discipline by Benjamin Barber:

“They have served the ideal of the enlightenment better than they have informed our political judgment. In substituting reason for common sense, they have declared the sense of commoners to be nonsense. Rights are philosophically vindicated, but only as abstractions that undermine democratic communities that breathe life into rights; justice is given an unimpeachable credential in epistemology, but no firm hold on action or on the deliberative process from which political action stems; talk is revivified as the heart of the political process and then recommended to citizens, but in a form that answers to constraints not of citizenship but of philosophy; civility is celebrated, but construed as incompatible with the sorts of collective human choice and communal purposes that give civility its political meaning; the past is resurrected, but only in order to disdain the present and mock the future.”

While many legal philosophers do, as Barber asserts, disdain the present and mock the future, most, like justices, are prone to suppose that their views are more consequential than in reality they are. They are disinclined to accept the reality that most audiences are no more influenced by moral reasoning than by what passes as legal reasoning. Richard Posner has ob- served the self-preoccupied aspect of work in moral philosophy: Moral philosophers pick from an ala carte menu the moral principles that coincide with the preferences of their social set, and they have both the intellec- tual agility to weave an inconsistent heap of policies into a superficially coherent unity and the psychological agility to honor their chosen principles only to the extent compatible with their personal happiness and professional advancement. Of course there are popular prophets who articulate a moral prece whose time has come, but whether the time for that precept has come heavily dependent on the experience of those to whom it is addressed. Lieber put it, “millions have died for similes… [but] politics are matters of realities not suppositions.” And many are the prophets of great eloquence and intellect who have been unable to find a receptive audience.

“No one is going to surrender his moral intuitions to moral theory, nor should he.”..

[Oliver Wendell] Holmes usefully cautioned us against relying too heavily on the moral language of the law, because it is chiefly an appeal to obedience and not an invitation to remake legal texts on the basis of more elevated moral reasoning. Changes in the moral language of the law will seldom if ever induce substantial changes in behavior or belief. Despite these enumerated disabilities, it remains a widely shared impulse of legal academics to discover, like astronomers, a new source of natural law, a new constellation of individual rights, to be invoked by life-tenured judges to decree the transformation of a gravely defective social order formed by an ignorant lumpenproletariat. An eminent example is Robin West, who finds in the inexhaustible text of the Fourteenth Amendment “anti-subordinationist” rights to be imposed as restrictions on democratic government.⁴² An overstated but pertinent criticism of her efforts is that

“Many of the new progressive strategies especially the suppression of free speech and the insistence that a radical vision is superior to that which the populace has developed over the years- are based on a profoundly antidemocratic misreading of the people’s choices…. [West] is ultimately an authoritarian in the deepest sense of the word, adopting traditional conservative tools to im- pose her outdated personal views on a public that has already soundly rejected them.”

There is, as one might expect, and as West exemplifies, a correlation be- tween the moral theorizing of legal academics and the dogma of “liberal” political correctness, because academic theory consistently favors, as Duncan Kennedy has listed: “Brown without delay and racial quotas, but civil disobedience, nonprosecution of draft card burners, the explicit consideration of distributive consequences rather than reliance on efficiency, judicial review of apportionment decisions, extensive constitutional protection of criminals’ rights, the constitutional protection of the right of homosexuals to engage in legislatively prohibited practices, the right to produce and consume pornography, and abortion rights.”

As Judge Posner has observed, there is often unresolved tension in this conven- tionality: “[They] favor abortion,… [but they] are against capital punishment…. They are for the theory of evolution when the question is whether creationism should be taught but against the theory of evolution when the question is whether there is a biological basis for differences in behavior between men and women. They want to regulate cigarette smoking out of existence, but they want to permit the smoking of marijuana. They are for the strongest possible public measures for safety and health, but they are against quarantining per- sons who are infected by the AIDS virus. 46 They denounce their predeces- sors for indifference to the fate of the Jews in Nazi Germany or the blacks in South Africa during apartheid, [but] have been for the most part indifferent to the genocides in Cambodia, Bosnia and Africa.”

West and others of like mind are thinking and writing about law. That is not visibly the case for some contemporary legal academics who, apparently despairing of their lack of influence on those who exercise political power, have withdrawn into a self-obsessive genre of literature celebrated as legal storytelling. Arthur Austin denotes them as Outsiders, against whom the “Empire Strikes Back.” While such art forms as legal story-telling may indeed be as irrelevant to law as Andy Warhol’s Campbell Soup cans are to artistic mastery, the Outsiders, like Andy Warhol, may be on to something. As a comment on the social utility of some of what passes for advanced legal scholarship, the Outsiders may have it about right.

On the other hand, one might wish to divert some of the energy of Outsiders to the vast and neglected opportunities to bring their humanity and intellect to the conduct of the more obscure public officers who run our cities, counties, school districts, and states, where modest gains in the pursuit of justice might be achieved, albeit without reward in the coin of academic status…

These disjunctions between academic thought about law and the work of courts or legislatures suggest that the legal academy bears little responsibility for the overbearing tendencies of the judiciary remarked in the previous chapters. What we may see are parallel, not sequential, developments within the legal profession. On the other hand, Frankfurter may have been accurate in describing the Supreme Court in its moments of hubris as seekers of the approval of the intellectual avant-garde.

While there were many academic critics of the Warren Court’s tendency to overreach its commission, their number diminished as those who remem- bered the 1930s were replaced by those who were attracted to law by their youthful hope to participate in broad social reform through constitutional litigation in federal courts. Those academicians who speculate as would-be Platonic Guardians are disposed to prefer that the Republic’s judges sit on a woolsack of discretion such as that of the feudal Court of Chancery and to applaud those who presume to do justice according to a ruling conscience or natural law that is at best the presumed wisdom of a ruling class.

For this reason, a vast amount of academic energy has been invested in the task of reconciling the constitutional role of the judiciary with democracy. Most of what can be usefully said on that subject was said at the time of ratification. For judges such as Cooley and Brandeis, the task of reconciliation was not especially difficult: Their view was that democratic legislation is valid unless explicitly proscribed by the text of a constitution ratified by the people and subject to modification by them; judicial review in their view is avowedly anti-democratic and should therefore be practiced with restraint assuring the moral and political primacy of legislation. However, the task of reconciliation becomes difficult and worthy of heroic intellectual efforts when thinking proceeds from the contrary premise that restraint should not be practiced and judges should be encouraged to enforce not only the text of constitutions, but also principles of natural law developed by academic discourse in political and moral philosophy.

Thus, an extensive academic literature argues that judicial review should be ever more intensive because of the deficiencies inherent in democratic legislation. Legislatures, it is said, are chiefly known as places in which we express our selfish impulses, an observation it would be difficult to contest. Because venal interest groups influence legislation, it is reasoned, government by decree emanating from the life-tenured elite is theoretically superior to democratic self-government. Others have striven to justify the overbearing conduct of the Supreme Court as a fulfillment of eighteenth-century republican expectations; these arguments tend to rest on the alleged congruence of the substance of the Court’s agenda with the politics of some founders. In essence, it has been suggested, the Court is somehow the real voice of the people, much as the king’s chancellor was the real voice of the Crown. Justice Brennan himself apparently deemed his principles to have the sanction of democratic self-government so long as the self-governing citizens accepted them, that is, did not rebel against his decisions. While he acknowledged the law he created and administered to be the product of his generation’s “experience and understanding, its passion and reason,” he was apparently untroubled that his passions were the product of his own experience and were not widely shared except among a limited professional class. Theories in this vein have been multiplied by academic authors, but a common theme has been that the Court should be more attentive to the advice of the moral philosophers of the academy and less attentive to “the common thoughts of men.”

Despite the enumerated limitations and overconfidence of legal academic theorists, their work has a synergistic effect. Academic theorists do, as Frankfurter observed, provide a receptive, sometimes even a fawning, audi- ence for heroic judges and give less frequent applause to text-bound legal doctrines. Justice Brennan, for example, could seemingly do no wrong. Even his extraordinary dissent in Michael H. v. Gerald D. received uncritical acceptance among theoreticians. Ronald Dworkin, Frank Michelman, and Kathleen Sullivan celebrated it as an exemplary “moral reading” of the Constitution, without expression of serious concern that such a moral read- ing is a finger in the eye of self-government.

While most theoreticians will on occasion acknowledge that not all morally correct opinions are also law, Judge Posner is not wrong to observe a tendency to conflation. That conflation is the risk feared by Brandeis when he questioned the teaching of philosophy. It tends to be a reason for the occasional attractions of academic moral philosophy to judges and the lawyers who appear before them. They, for the reasons stated by Mill, tend to be attracted to ideas empowering themselves. If the Holmesian lightning bolt of genius is that courts ought to be less constrained and more aggressive in the exercise of their powers, many judges and lawyers will experience a self-inflationary gratification from the message. A dramatic example of academic theory that may be taken too seriously by judges and lawyers is the discovery by academicians of international human rights law as a category of our national law…

These scholars reveal customary international law as yet another form of unenacted natural law to be enforced by life-tenured judges. That law is based on what judges call concern about current international conventions not ratified by the United States, or conceptions of justice in other countries around the world, about which the primary sources of information are the academic authors who urge its enforcement. For example, the South African Constitutional Court in 1995 was induced to decide the constitutionality of capital punishment substantially on the basis of international precedents; this is presented as a model for a global system to be enforced in the United States by the federal judiciary.

In early times, the federal courts were charged to enforce the law of admiralty having its origins in international practice and understanding and to customary law governing the relations between nations, such as the law of diplomatic immunity. In recent years, lower federal courts have in addition asserted jurisdiction to enforce customary international law of other sorts. The American Law Institute has now lent its support to the idea that customary international law, as discerned by the federal judiciary, is federal law, perhaps superseding even prior federal legislation. While not long ago it was possible to suppose that customary international human rights law was narrowly limited to such matters as genocide and torture, we are now told that the list is not closed and has, due to improved communications around the globe, grown to include gender discrimination, religious rights, rights relating to sexual orientation, and the right to be free from “hate speech.”

We are also told by contemporary Langdells that life-tenured judges “find,” and do not “make,” such customary international law, and we are assured that, also among the rights to be protected, is the right to live in a democratic society. The irony of this last assurance seems to be invisible to those who give it, nor does it dissuade life-tenured federal judges from repairing to Colorado in the summertime to attend seminars on customary international human rights law conducted by experts in that field. Or constrain other efforts to persuade the judiciary that they are members of “a global community” and that an international outlook on moral issues is more appropriate than obedience to the conventionalities of insensitive American habitats. When it was observed that the expansion of customary international law to include unenacted laws regarding “human rights” threatens to effect a vast displacement of state law made by judges and legislators who are accountable to the people they serve, Harold Koh responded by expressing disdain for state and local law, and for the right to self-government. For him, any matter having even secondary international effects is an appropriate subject for federalization pursuant to the foreign affairs powers of the federal government. If the federal courts have long decided the scope of diplomatic immunity, then it is in this view but a modest step for them to decide whether capital punishment violates an international norm. Nor should it matter that the United States has refused to ratify a particular convention, or has ratified it only subject to conditions precluding its appli- cation to displace state law. Koh seems to hope that if the life-tenured federal judiciary were not to impose as customary international law of their own devising (reflecting the presumably elevated morality of human rights scholars), American states might practice genocide on their citizens.

There was for a time a substantial evangelical campaign to transfer American legal traditions to developing countries. That campaign was aborted when its champions recognized that the economic and social infrastructure of the receiving nations is so different with respect to such matters as class and tribal rivalries that the American experience was simply inap- plicable. It is for the same reason nonsense to suppose that the issue of capital punishment, much less that of “hate speech,” can be universalized. It is amply difficult for American judges to resolve such issues in the context of an American culture of which they have at least some knowledge; to involve them in the administration of natural law principles derived from the whole of human experience is a form of cultural imperialism. It is also an invitation to judicial arrogance desensitizing the American legal profession to its responsibility for our own democratic institutions.

What is frequently lacking in much academic legal discourse is attention to those aspects of legal institutions that generate the loyalty of the citizens expected to sustain them by their obedience. As Burke said, “[I]n the groves of their academy, at the end of every vista, you see nothing but gallows. Nothing is left which engages the affections on the part of the commonwealth.” Rarely is recognition given in academic literature to the role of law as a confirmation of conventional morality and as a message of reason- able to the good citizens who do the Republic’s work that it is indeed their Republic.

While there is thus a synergy between these phenomena, the inter-relationships between heroic judging and theoretical scholarship are likely minor effects. As Lieber (who learned it from Savigny) and his adherents would have been quick to affirm, both developments are surely driven by larger forces operating within the legal profession and derived from the larger culture of which they are a part. Judges and professors, as well as many lawyers, are members of Wiebe’s “national class.” Their thoughts are the product of an industrial era, an age that believed all things possible, and even the remaking of a self-governing society into a utopia “void of crime and poverty” by technical experts on the bench. And they are also the product of a time when the Republic came to fill the role of a global empire threatened by an evil adversary that…personified mob rule. …It is the imperial America that has made the legal profession what it is at the end of the twentieth century, not the legal profession that made America.

Justice Byron White served as contrarian to the Supreme Court in the heroic age of Justice Brennan.

ChatGPT summarizes reactions to this book:

The critiques in Stewards of Democracy (1999) hit nerves across multiple camps, and the reactions split along predictable ideological and professional lines:

1. Within the Legal Academy

Carrington’s argument—that judges and legal academics had drifted into a self-anointed priesthood, cut off from democratic accountability—was provocative. Many legal academics dismissed it as reactionary or nostalgic for a “formalist” era when judges restrained themselves. Scholars invested in the Warren and Brennan legacies defended the Court’s “moral readings” of the Constitution, arguing Carrington undervalued the real-world benefits of rights expansion. But others, especially law-and-democracy scholars, echoed his warnings that the Court and academy had become too enamored with abstract theory and insufficiently attentive to self-government.

2. Among Judges and Practitioners

Judges sympathetic to judicial restraint—those in the mold of Frankfurter or Byron White—saw Carrington as articulating what they had long thought: that the Court was drifting into policymaking, issuing decrees without democratic legitimacy. Practicing lawyers, especially outside the elite “national class,” tended to resonate with his criticism of the legal academy’s academic drift and jargon-laden irrelevance.

3. Political and Cultural Reception

Politically, conservatives embraced the book as intellectual ammunition against “judicial activism,” citing its critique of Brennan-style jurisprudence and the elevation of judicial elites over elected legislatures. Liberals, by contrast, often brushed it off as overblown or selectively focused on excesses while ignoring moments (like Brown v. Board) where judicial intervention was widely celebrated. The book’s sharp linkage of judicial liberalism with the rise of a disconnected “meritocratic national class” drew fire as elitist-bashing, but also found sympathy from communitarian critics like Michael Sandel.

4. Long-Term Influence

The book didn’t cause a tidal wave but it fed into a broader late-90s/early-2000s skepticism about judicial supremacy. It was cited in debates over the Rehnquist and early Roberts Courts, and in critiques of legal academia’s embrace of abstract “theory” over practical law. The strongest aftershocks were in legal education reform debates, where Carrington’s attack on “academization” was taken seriously even by those who didn’t share his constitutional pessimism.

Legal academy: Many scholars invested in the Warren/Brennan legacy pushed back, defending “moral readings” of the Constitution; others (communitarian/democracy-first types) echoed Carrington’s warning that courts and the academy drifted from self-government.

Snapshot of specific reviews (law journals)

  • Jeffrey O’Connell & Thomas E. O’Connell, review in Journal of Law & Politics 16:479–498 (2000) — extended engagement with Carrington’s “democratic law” thesis.
  • Francis A. Allen, “Law and the Waning of Democratic Values,” Green Bag 2d, vol. 4, no. 1 (Autumn 2000) — framed the book within broader concerns about self-rule.
  • Patrick O. Gudridge, “Carrington, Cooley, Kennedy, Klare” (2001) — situates Carrington among wider jurisprudential debates on democracy.
  • Robert Post, “The Supreme Court Opinion as Institutional Practice” (2001) — cites Carrington in exploring judicial practice and democratic legitimacy.
  • Paul D. Carrington – Selected Law Review Articles

  • Of Law and the River, 34 Journal of Legal Education 222–228 (1984) — foundational essay on legal education, widely cited.
  • The Revolutionary Idea of University Legal Education, 31 William & Mary Law Review 527–574 (1990) — delivered as the George Wythe Lecture, exploring legal education reform.
  • Diversity!, Utah Law Review (1992) — provocative critique of the diversity movement in legal academia.
  • Judicial Independence & Court Reform

  • Original Sin and Judicial Independence: Providing Accountability for Justices (with Roger C. Cramton), 50 William & Mary Law Review 1105 (2009) — proposes mechanisms for Supreme Court accountability.
  • Judicial Independence in Excess: Reviving the Judicial Duty of the Supreme Court (with Roger C. Cramton), 94 Cornell Law Review 587 (2009) — critiques the Court’s drift into policymaking and suggests reforms.
  • Other Notable Essays & Reviews

  • The Price of Legal Education, Harvard Law Review Forum (2013) — on tuition, costs, and ABA’s role in legal education.
  • Public Funding of Judicial Campaigns: The North Carolina Experience and the Activism of the Supreme Court, 89 North Carolina Law Review 1965 (2011) — explores judicial elections and campaign funding.
  • Continuing Work on the Civil Rules: The Summons, 63 Notre Dame Law Review 733 (2014) — technical essay on civil procedure reform.
  • Writing Other Peoples’ Constitutions, 33 North Carolina Journal of International Law 167 (2017) — analysis of constitutional transplants and legal export.
  • Beyond his controversial book Stewards of Democracy, Carrington stirred debate in academia with pieces like Diversity! and his co-authored essays on judicial independence. Other works, while less polemical, cemented his influence in civil procedure, legal education, and court reform.

    Posted in Law | Comments Off on Stewards Of Democracy: Law As Public Profession (1999)

    Why Is The Elite Media Singing From The Same Hymnal About The Trump-Putin Summit? (8-17-25)

    01:00 Why Do Elite News Operations Sound So Dumb So Often? https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162886
    13:00 Industrial Policy’s Potential with Marc Fasteau and Ian Fletcher, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=MykCxs4aFl4
    21:00 Yoram Hazony: The Man Driving the Nationalist Revival on the Right, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162566
    1:08:00 Industrial Policy for the United States: Winning the Competition for Good Jobs and High-Value Industries (2025), https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162358
    1:17:00 Attitudes to AI are a rorschach’s test
    1:34:00 Megyn Kelly on Russiagate and the New York Times, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162867
    1:40:00 The Prestige Economy, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162904
    1:50:00 The Engineered Chinese State Vs Lawyerly America, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162900
    1:52:00 Ira Israel: Could Enlightenment Mean Accepting Our Own Insignificance?, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162921
    2:03:00 The most powerful systems of epistemic closure in America today, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162850
    2:20:00 Russiagate and the New York Times, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162867
    2:30:00 The Politics of Expertise, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162857
    2:55:00 What Goes Unsaid In Stephen P. Turner’s Autobiography Mad Hazard: A Life in Social Theory?, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162822
    3:58:00 Individualism Is Not A Right-Wing Value, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162613
    4:01:00 ‘The Making of the American Conservative Mind: National Review and Its Times’ (2005), https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162696

    Grok says:

    Luke Ford (aka Fordy) demonstrates a reasonable degree of self-awareness in parts of the transcript, such as when he explicitly acknowledges his own incentives for promoting alternative narratives (e.g., “I have very strong incentives to buy into conspiracy theories… because I just can’t repeat back to you what other people do more effectively”). He also admits to his right-wing hero system and personal background influences (e.g., his upbringing, conversions, and resentment toward “cool kids”). However, there are several areas where he lacks self-awareness, often manifesting as hypocrisy, projection, or failure to apply his own critiques inward. Below, I outline key instances, grouped thematically, with supporting quotes and reasoning. These highlight inconsistencies between his stated principles (e.g., valuing truth over prestige, avoiding groupthink) and his behavior or rhetoric.

    1. Hypocrisy in Critiquing Media Groupthink and Prestige Economies

    Ford repeatedly accuses elite media of “singing from the same hymnal” due to prestige-seeking, incentives for conformity, and epistemic closure (ignoring contrary evidence to protect a “hero system”). Yet, he exhibits similar patterns in his own monologue, echoing alt-media tropes (e.g., lab leak theories, critiques of immigration assimilation) without acknowledging how this aligns him with a niche “herd” for his own status in alternative circles. This suggests a blind spot: he sees himself as an outsider truth-teller but doesn’t recognize his content as a mirror of the prestige economy he decries.

    Example: He says, “Why is it the people who hold the most prestige frequently say the dumbest things? And it comes to me that often belonging to any group requires a certain amount of singing from the same hymnal… You have to say these stupid things to maintain your standing among the cool kids in the elite news media.”

    Lack of self-awareness: Ford positions himself as exempt from this, but his monologue frequently parrots unorthodox views (e.g., “groups do not tend to assimilate in a profound way… Japanese Americans have certain life results that are more similar to the life results of the Japanese in Japan”) that align with right-wing online communities. He doesn’t reflect on how this might be his own “hymnal” for audience capture or personal prestige in dissident spaces, especially as a YouTuber seeking views.

    Example: “The prestige economy is not the same as the merit economy… Credibility will largely flow from status, not from telling the truth. You will raise your status, not by telling the truth, generally speaking, but by assimilating to the high status position.”

    Lack of self-awareness: Ford critiques this system but builds his show around contrarian takes (e.g., conspiracy-friendly framings of Russia Gate or Biden’s senility) that boost his niche status. He admits incentives for uniqueness but doesn’t probe how his “truth-seeking” might be performative, akin to the media’s “neutrality” facade he mocks.

    2. Projection of Epistemic Closure and Hero Systems Onto Others

    Ford draws on Ernest Becker’s “hero systems” and epistemic closure to explain why people (e.g., media elites) shield themselves from contrary views to maintain meaning and identity. He applies this astutely to others but rarely turns it inward, overlooking how his own right-wing hero system (e.g., nationalism, group interests over individualism) creates similar blinders. This is ironic given his emphasis on self-reflection.

    Example: “With every hero system comes a system of epistemic closure… You are shielded from all arguments that can contradict or undermine your hero system… No matter what happens, people almost never change their mind.”

    Lack of self-awareness: Ford identifies as a “man of the right” and admits his hero system shifted (e.g., from Protestantism to encountering Dennis Prager and Judaism), but he doesn’t examine how his current views (e.g., skepticism of diversity’s benefits: “The more diverse America becomes… the less Americans have in common”) might involve closure. For instance, he dismisses liberal critiques (e.g., Ezra Klein’s interview style as partisan) without considering if his own framing (e.g., portraying media as uniformly biased against Trump) is equally closed-off to pro-establishment evidence.

    Example: “If you get humiliated often enough with your particular hero system… you will start to look for alternatives and then you’ll become open to contrary points of view.”

    Lack of self-awareness: Ford shares personal humiliations (e.g., resentment toward “cool kids” excluding him for merit/truth pursuits: “It’s normal to feel some resentment… Why don’t I have their status?”) but frames them as making him wiser, not as fueling his own epistemic biases. He doesn’t reflect on how this resentment might drive his anti-elite rants, projecting “humiliation” dynamics onto media without seeing it in himself.

    3. Inconsistent Stance on Individualism vs. Group Loyalty

    Ford critiques individualism as a “left-wing” trait (e.g., incompatible with right-wing values like duty, hierarchy, and group interests), praising collective systems (e.g., nationalism, tribalism). However, his life story and presentation reveal a highly individualistic path—conversions, personal intellectual journeys, and a solo YouTube show—which he doesn’t reconcile with his ideology. This shows a disconnect between his preached values and lived experience.

    Example: “Individualism is some key essential right-wing value… And in this new biography of William F. Buckley is repeatedly described as an individualist… But he doesn’t come across as particularly right-wing.”Lack of self-awareness: Ford lambasts Buckley and National Review figures (e.g., Frank Meyer, Russell Kirk) as “individualists” unfit for true conservatism, yet his own narrative is individualistic: e.g., “I moved to America… America has much more veneration of the individual… I formed a right-wing hero system… I read this book… it makes the point…” He describes solitary pursuits (e.g., reading Becker, interviewing academics) without noting the irony that his “right-wing” identity seems self-constructed, not dutifully inherited from a group/tradition.

    Example: “Right-wing moral reasoning is not every man for himself… That’s every man in his place in service of the group… Your role is to align yourself with these external standards.”

    Lack of self-awareness: Ford emphasizes group duty but hosts a show that’s “every man for himself” (solo rants, personal anecdotes like “I have made great progress on many of my dates” without “official pronouncements”). He critiques Protestantism/evangelicalism for individual focus (“rejects traditional… holds fast the literal words of scripture and the power of the individual”) but doesn’t address how his own Protestant upbringing and conversions echo this “left-wing” individualism.

    Joke 1: The Hymnal Hypocrisy
    “Luke Ford walks into a room and says, ‘Why’s everyone singing from the same media hymnal? Bunch of prestige-chasing sheep!’ Then he grabs his YouTube mic, belts out the alt-right’s greatest hits, and wonders why the room’s chanting, ‘Luke, you’re leading the choir!'”

    Joke 2: Hero System Blind Spot
    “Luke’s reading Ernest Becker, shouting, ‘Everyone’s trapped in their hero system, shielding themselves from truth!’ Meanwhile, his right-wing hero system’s so strong, it’s got a fortress, a moat, and a ‘No Liberals Allowed’ sign. Self-awareness? Luke says, ‘What’s that, a conspiracy theory?'”

    Joke 3: Individualist in Denial
    “Luke says, ‘Right-wingers love duty, not individualism—that’s left-wing nonsense!’ Then he spends four hours monologuing solo on YouTube about his personal journey from Australia to Prager to Judaism. Luke, buddy, you’re so individualistic, you’re basically a one-man tribe!”

    Joke 4: Dating Anecdote Disaster
    “Luke goes, ‘I made great progress on my dates, no official pronouncements needed!’ Then he wonders why his dates ghost him when he starts lecturing about epistemic closure mid-dinner. Luke, maybe they just didn’t want to join your hero system!”

    ChatGPT:

    1. Media groupthink vs. your own hymnal

    “The cool kids have to say dumb things to stay in their group. Me? I just say dumb things on YouTube for free.”

    2. Prestige economy hypocrisy

    “I rail against the prestige economy… then brag about my $186 Financial Times subscription like it’s a Rolex.”

    “I said credibility comes from status, not truth. Which is why I keep quoting Ernest Becker like he’s my Costco card.”

    3. Hero systems projection

    “I explain how nobody ever changes their hero system. Then I tell you about how I changed mine five times before breakfast.”

    “I say resentment drives elite media… while I’m still mad the cool kids didn’t let me sit at their lunch table in 1984.”

    4. Individualism vs. collectivism

    “I preach that the right is about duty to the group, not individualism. Then I fire up my solo livestream and rant for three hours about my dates.”

    “Nothing says ‘group loyalty’ like moving countries, changing religions twice, and starting your own YouTube channel.”

    5. Dating ‘progress’ metaphor

    “I said just because the media doesn’t announce progress doesn’t mean it didn’t happen. Just like my dates. Sure, there’s no press release—but trust me, history was made.”

    “The Pentagon should issue my dating life as an official statement: vague, no measurable progress, but technically still ongoing.”

    Gemini:

    On projecting his own biases onto others:

    “He says everyone has a ‘hero system’ that creates blind spots, but then he goes on a rant about how his own hero system makes him ‘wiser.’ That’s like a fish giving a lecture on the dangers of water”.

    “He uses his resentment toward the ‘cool kids’ to explain why the media is bad, but he doesn’t realize he’s just auditioning for a new cool kids club”.

    On being an individualist while advocating for group loyalty:

    “He criticizes individualism and praises group loyalty, which is an interesting take for a guy with a solo show named after himself”.

    “He says he’s a ‘man of the right,’ but his life story is the most individualistic thing you could imagine: leaving one religion, finding another, and starting his own intellectual journey on YouTube. He’s a one-man group.”

    Posted in America | Comments Off on Why Is The Elite Media Singing From The Same Hymnal About The Trump-Putin Summit? (8-17-25)