Law professor Paul D. Carrington wrote:
* American law in the last half-century has been increasingly disdainful of the expressed wishes and expectations of the citizens it purports to serve.
* Robert Wiebe, for example, has identified World War II as marking the general ascendancy to controlling power of what he denotes as the “national class,” a ruling class including many lawyers and most judges and law teachers, and, of course, much of the media. The “national class” of lawyers identifies itself by credentials, mostly academic credentials. Its members tend to lack connections to and sympathy for an increasingly alienated underclass who have ceased to see themselves as participants in government. Members of this “national class” are prone to disdain the messy moral compromises of elective politics, perhaps especially local politics, and hence envision constitutional adjudication as the appropriate means of resolving conflicts of moral import.
Thus, in our moment of prosperity and world domination, while we insist on the virtues of self-government in every corner of the globe, we are forgetting its value to ourselves. As perceptive foreign observers writing for The Economist in 1998 could see, American lawyers, judges, and even politicians are increasingly given to “ramming down the throats of voters policies which they have not endorsed,” at the very moment that other Americans are wisely demanding the right to self-government for people in such distant places as Kosovo, Malaysia, and Iraq. We are in too many respects, as Mary Ann Glendon has put it, a nation under lawyers.
* Thomas Cooley: “The strength of law lies in its commonplace character; and it becomes feeble and untrustworthy when it expresses something different from the common thoughts of
men.”
* It is today the conventional wisdom among the ‘national class’ that electing judges is a bad idea, that judges ought to hold tenure for life, as federal judges do. The reason generally given for this view is, of course, that judges enforcing individual rights provided in constitutions must inhibit, and should not be intimidated by, but must be independent of, majoritarian politics. In this view, the Supreme Court of the United States is a paradigm of political virtue because it is structurally indifferent to the moral judgment of any democratic electorate.
* The concept of a “liberal” krytocracy [rule by judges] — one fired by a desire to transform the social order it governs — may have unique at the time of its advent in post-World War II, post-Brown America.
Perhaps the leading twentieth-century practitioner of constitutional law-making in disregard of the rights of citizens to govern themselves was William Brennan… [T]he inflated sense of the Court’s role he seems to be have brought to its work helped to make the Court to resemble a College of Cardinals telling members of the faith what to believe and how to live. The Brennan “encyclicals” required the community to respect a broad range of individual and minority rights, and left little discretion to local congregations or constituencies to believe, or to act upon the belief, that somewhat more communitarianism and less individualism or pluralism might be preferable. The encyclicals were not presented as serious interpretations of a written legal text, but were rooted in natural law sanctioned by reference to the indeterminate text of the Fourteenth Amendment and to what Justice Brennan presumed to be the better instincts and ideals of the people. He was fairly said to be a non-interpretivist engaged in “a search for political-moral knowledge, for answers to the various questions as to how we, the polity, should live our public, collective life, or life in common” and sometimes our not so public life, too. Unlike Cooley or Brandeis, Brennan seldom if ever gave weight to the political judgment of elected officers, perhaps especially those elected at state or local levels. Frankfurter only somewhat unjustly described the Brennan Court as animated by “self-willed, self-righteous power lust.” Whether lustful or not, the Court embraced the belief that anything a legislature could do, it could do better.
There is irony in the denotation of this anti-democratic restoration of judicial supremacy as “liberal,” a sort of code word for the moral preferences of the recently emerged “national class.” As Christopher Lasch explained the irony, many ruling meritocrats revolted against the moral values of those less-esteemed persons who merely vote, pay taxes, bear and raise the Republic’s children, and put themselves at risk in its defense. A visible means of avoiding the noisome duty of persuading these lesser persons of the correct world view was to constitutionalize political issues that would otherwise be subjects of popular governance. The meritocracy in revolt may, if Lasch is correct, have supplied the receptive audience needed to induce high court judges to discard the caution advocated by earlier “liberals” favoring the right to self-government. Indeed, Frankfurter despised that his colleagues were determined to be immortalized in “the Valhalla of liberty” and “in the meantime to have the avant-gard of the Yale Law School…praise them.”
A different interpretation is that of Michael Sandel, who blames the Supreme Court for displacing the earlier American tradition of shared power with a new vision of “freedom” elevating individual autonomy and governmental neutrality at the expense of the bonds uniting us in a common venture. men venture. Evidence to support his hypothesis can be found not only in the conduct of the Court, but also in legal scholarship disregarding the possibility that life-tenured judges ought to or could be influenced in the formulation of doctrine by “the common thoughts of men” or other communitarian concerns, expressing wonder that anyone should be concerned about the Court’s “anti-majoritarianism” and dismissing the concern as platitudinous.
Whatever the social-psychological origins of this anti-democratic “liberalism,” it called into question the validity and integrity of the traditional political rhetoric of the Republic. Life-tenured judges are not in any useful sense “we, the people,” however much one might wish to believe otherwise. To speak of krytocracy as a government of or by the people is a transparent fraud on citizens’ political rights. While none can deny, as Justice Robert Jackson affirmed, that the “very purpose” of constitutions is
“to withdraw certain subjects from the vicissitudes of political controversy,” when “certain subjects” include many or most of those of greatest interest to citizens, the effect, as he noted, is to withdraw the life-giving oxygen from the air sustaining self-government.
As we have seen, our exemplars were mindful of at least three grave problems inherent in political rule by judges. First, as Cooley’s message at Harvard reflected, they believed that a judiciary disregarding the “common thoughts of men” will be resisted by those whose thoughts it disdains. In this view, people do not change their minds, and often not even their behavior, because of the utterances of senior citizens in black robes, especially if they are imbued with the individualist spirit of Protestantism. Judgments of high courts purporting to effect social change are therefore often useless and sometimes counterproductive. On the other hand, Cooley and his successors supposed that people will more readily adapt to policies debated and decided by democratic methods in which they participated, especially if their dissenting views have been prudently accommodated. Second, my exemplars recognized that judges as a class are not selected for their political and moral wisdom, nor is there reason or experience to suggest that they acquire it in office. “Wayward” as Hand observed the vagaries of popular assemblies” to be, judges of all political persuasions are capable of equally colossal political blunders. There are at least three reasons for this. One is that the judicial process is not well suited to the presentation and assimilation of political wisdom. The Brandeis brief to the contrary notwithstanding, legislatures and administrative rulemakers are, as Freund observed, structurally more adept at “mastering statistics and economics,” as Holmes prescribed, because they have direct access to technical expertise as well as to popular estimates of such expertise and have no obligation to address an imminent dispute when they have well-founded doubt about the right solution. A second reason, as Freund emphasized, is that the judiciary can seldom broker prudent compromise between competing values, and compromise is more often than not the wisest policy. That “the best is the enemy of the good” is an adverse comment on much judicial policymaking. A third reason is that the doctrine of precedent to which American courts are necessarily committed dictates that they cannot readily correct their policymaking mistakes. Having written, the judicial hand moves on. For all these reasons, political blunders by the judiciary may be more likely and more costly, even though they are more likely to bear the marks of principled decisionmaking…
The efforts of judges to transform the social order without the general moral support of the citizens are not very effective and are often counterproductive…
After Brown, it seemed that every beleaguered individual group in America, including perhaps some beleaguered only in their own perceptions, fancied that the court in its anti-democratic role might relieve their distress. The idea of popular sovereignty came to be viewed by many American lawyers…as a mere impediment to social reform. And the role of the federal judiciary became once again redolent of the overbearing and pretentious role of the chancellor wielding power in the name of the king’s conscience…
While Brown stands as the shining example of the good deeds that politically animated, life-tenured judges may on occasion perform when their decisions are congruent with widely shared moral precepts, even the Court’s performance with respect to racial segregation is mixed and can be said at times to manifest misuse of its political power. When the Court at last ordered lower federal courts to reorganize and manage the public schools, and not merely in the South where segregation was de jure, it pitted its authority broadly against self-government in communities spread across the continent…
The spirit of Southern rednecks who wanted to impeach Earl Warren was nationalized in the politics of George Wallace, the angry governor of Alabama, who by denouncing the “pointy-headed intellectuals” marshaled a huge vote in the 1968 Democratic primaries in northern states. Many individual federal judges were subject to strenuous efforts to intimidate them; numerous Michigan bumper stickers called not for the impeachment, but the assassination, of Judge Stephen Roth for ordering bussed integration of all the schools in metropolitan Detroit, one of many cities in which school populations reflected segregated housing patterns caused in minor part by historic misuses of local political power reflecting racist impulses. That extremely hostile reaction was most visible in the westside suburbs, which were populated by the offspring of twentieth-century immigrants from eastern Europe who bore no responsibility for historic harms and who perceived no reason why their children should bear the burden and inconvenience of desegregating African-American children for sins they did not commit. Judge Roth, himself an immigrant, was likely responding in his order to the evidence that the burden of desegregation, if limited to the city of Detroit, would fall entirely on those least responsible for it and leave free of any inconvenience the monied, “national” class residing in Grosse Pointe and Bloomfield Hills. While an appeal from his order was pending, he died of a heart attack, quite possibly caused by the stress associated with the odium attached to his decision.
The effect outside the South was to uproot neighborhood schools in black neighborhoods as well as white. Sacrificed in the effort to promote racial integration was the traditional relationship between public education and the family. Derrick Bell, made the point that it was not merely white parents, but also black, whose responsibility and authority over the education of their children was diminished. There is even reason to suspect that the psychological justifications for desegregation were harmfully
self-fulfilling, perhaps even foreseeably so. While it would be unjust to suggest that there was a clearly superior approach to the achievement of public school desegregation or to blame the Court for the poor estate of public education in America at the century’s end, Brown II and its progeny surely made a contribution to the demise of public schools. And, over the longer term, public education as a means by which citizens share the tutelage of their children may be more vital to the Republic than the Constitution itself. On that account, the federal courts have substantially but belatedly abandoned the goal of racial integration of school children as one that is both unattainable and counterproductive. In the extensions of its application, Brown II has indeed been silently overruled.
School desegregation was the defining moment for the “liberal” Court and profession, but it was only a point of departure. With equally high purpose, the Court soon undertook by judicial decree to transform other aspects of American society. Near the top of the agenda was the transformation of state and local police…
The Court in 1964 went beyond its moral and political support in regulating police conduct. In a pivotal case, it held that the Fourteenth Amendment prohibited a state from using a confession secured by questioning conducted before the accused consulted his counsel. And, a year later, it held that the state must advise the accused of his right to counsel before questioning, else a conviction based in part on his confession must be reversed. These decisions were not well-received by those whose obedience was required, for at least three reasons. First, they appeared to require radical change in the customary practices of local police departments everywhere. Second, they coincided with a precipitous increase in violent crime in most American cities. Third, they resulted in the release of persons, many or most of whom were almost certainly guilty of serious crime…
The Court also undertook the reformation of state prisons. There can be no doubt of the squalid conditions of many of them, but whether judges run materially more humane prisons than wardens remains open to debate…
Justice Brennan in his retirement cheerfully forecast that “one day the Court will outlaw the death penalty. Permanently.” It seems never to have occurred to him that the abolition of capital punishment is properly a task for those who write and amend the constitutions and laws of the states and not for his College of Cardinals to decide without regard for citizens’ rights to self-government…
Among the most lawless of Justice Brennan’s opinions was his decision to savage by subtle means the popular institution of the right to jury trial in civil cases…
There is no principle of natural law by which the line between church and state can be judged. While justices may suppose that “the dissemination of science” is a “sufficient agent” of civic moral education to sustain a community capable of self-government, theirs is a “culture of disbelief.” The contrary belief of the Founders that religious life is needed to sustain the ties of community essential to democratic government is another that has not been falsified…
The new age of judicial heroics tracked the advent of the legal academy… Felix Frankfurter declared… “law and lawyers are what the law schools make them.” …industrialization creating Americans’ appetite for technical competence certified by academic credentials…
Since [1900], the legal academy has been drifting into the academic profession and away from the legal profession… The academic profession in America has at least since 1950 outranked the legal profession in social status, to those preoccupied with affect, the doctorate in philosophy in any discipline is a more luminous achievement than a mere law degree and license…
Academization threatens the very benefits it confers by reducing the prospect that studious authors will be taken seriously by those bearing public responsibility. If Holmes’s lightning of genius should strike a law professor today, it is unlikely that “the real world” would notice. The reasons for this are enumerated below. First, academic lawyers achieve status within their profession less by performing useful service to the Republic than by meeting conventional academic standards requiring the utterance of novel ideas pitched to a high level of abstraction. “The remoter and more general aspects of the law are those which give it universal interest,” Holmes said. In pursuing what seem to be issues of universal dimension, academicians tend to forego study of those lesser ones that they might be able to solve and on which public officers are likely to accept their counsel. The tendency to engage in cosmology, or what Linda Mullenix has denoted as “metarealism,” is likely reinforced by the increase in the number of law teachers holding doctorates in other more esteemed disciplines. Ironically, metarealism, even in the extreme form of nihilism denying the integrity of legal texts, is in post-modern diction often denoted as “pragmatism. Yet, as Charles Collier noted, there is very little legal scholarship today resembling three prosaic articles appearing together in an early issue of the Harvard Law Review: Brandeis and Warren, “The Law of Ponds”; Beale, “Tickets”; or Williston, “Successive Promises of the Same Performance.” Instead, legal scholars are prone to exhibit their mastery of almost any other discipline than law.
Second, most large legal ideas were entertained in the time of Justinian, if not even in the time of Hammurabi. There are no new continents of law to explore. Academic lawyers are in this respect in an unfortunate position not unlike that of gross anatomists, who have no hope of discovering a new organ in the human body and are therefore scorned by their medical re- search colleagues who have large mysteries to pierce and whose literature may achieve seeming miracles. This appears to be the realization expressed by Holmes when he quit academic life for the bench. Third, as Cooley remarked at Harvard, and as Cicero and Thucydides had previously observed, sound, useful legal ideas are generally conven- tional ones. So even Holmes conceded that law must respect “the habits of a particular people at a particular time.” “The life of the law is not logic, but experience,” he said in his most famous utterance. Good law expresses the culture of which it is a part and is therefore confined by the moral premises of that culture.
Ernst Freund made the point that: “It is not possible to work a [legal] system successfully if its fundamental justifi- cation is constantly questioned; or putting it the other way, a great system that has established itself will convert its disciples from skeptics into votaries, or will quickly get rid of them. Law, like other human institutions, is a working compromise, and the very fact that it is an appeal to reason demands assump- tions that must not be too closely questioned.”
This reality is odious to academicians of pure heart who regard it as their duty and their privilege to question all the premises of the social order. In this respect, there is a fundamental, but seldom noted, conflict of interest in academic law. Fourth, cloistered scholars are physically isolated from the universe in which real decisions are made. Sound moral judgment on public issues is an attribute not easily acquired within the academic cloister. To be useful advisers and critics to those exercising public responsibility, legal scholars would need to involve themselves in active politics to a degree that few do. Thus, in 1896 Woodrow Wilson, then president of Princeton University, deplored the tendency of professional academics to treat texts as “material” and “not life”; they do not, he said, reflect, so much as “they set forth schemes, [and] expound with dispassionate method.” “Their minds,” he perceived, “are not stages, but museums; nothing is done there, but very curious and valuable collections are kept there.”
Fifth, for reasons implicit in the foregoing observations, the academic enterprise encourages utopian dogmatization. It does not reward the practice of moral compromise, which…is the objective of democratic policies and law. The complex constitutional structure of the Republic was designed precisely to prevent the political implementation of dogma, to compel compromise… Utopianism in the academy has been reinforced by the tendency of the heroic judiciary to perform the role of Cardinals willing to issue decrees to effect all manner of benign results.
Sixth, public decisions…are reactive to immediacies… Even judges and lawyers sympathetic to positions taken by academics infrequently have time or energy to consult academic literature with the care required by turgid academic prose.
Seventh, academic authors are often disinclined to accept the modest role…as mere secondary authorities… To write such work [as 1883’s A Treatise on the Constitutional Limitations Which Rest upon the Legislative Power of the States of the American Union by Thomas M. Cooley], authors must eschew novel thoughts and to that extent disavow not only academic status seeking but the more immediate satisfactions of self-expression…
Eighth, work on intellectual frontiers…often employs the professional jargon of another academic discipline, a jargon likely to impede, if it does not prevent, comprehension by judges and practicing lawyers… The university law school is increasingly a colonial outpost of the graduate school. A self-respecting law school serving the “national class” would be ashamed not to have on its faculty a broad sampling of scholars whose in- terests in law is incidental to a primary intellectual interest in another more academically respectable field, an interest certified by a doctorate in that field. Their work is often difficult to communicate effectively to persons outside the pertinent intellectual community.
Ninth, academic status is seldom acquired by work on the law and politics of local institutions. For the most respected academic lawyers, only the federal government or the international order is worthy of study. Work of the sort done by Freund with state and local governments is out of fashion because it does not command the attention and admiration of the “national class.”
These enumerated circumstances have an aspect of self-fulfilling proph- ecy. Teachers and writers who do not expect a hearing from those in power and not to invest themselves in the effort to address the nonexistent audience in ways that would be helpful to it. As a consequence, …much that now passes for scholarship by law professors is not written with an expectation that it might be read and used by those having public responsibility, with whom academic authors find little or no common ground. It is often discourse addressed to small audiences of specialized academic readers having little involvement in the immediate cares of the world. Academic lawyers therefore frequently achieve the fate of being ignored by those whom they ignore. Indeed, it may be questioned whether many legal academics are still lawyers or instead have become political philosophers. As such, they may be subject to the complaint made against some of the most eminent members of that esteemed discipline by Benjamin Barber:
“They have served the ideal of the enlightenment better than they have informed our political judgment. In substituting reason for common sense, they have declared the sense of commoners to be nonsense. Rights are philosophically vindicated, but only as abstractions that undermine democratic communities that breathe life into rights; justice is given an unimpeachable credential in epistemology, but no firm hold on action or on the deliberative process from which political action stems; talk is revivified as the heart of the political process and then recommended to citizens, but in a form that answers to constraints not of citizenship but of philosophy; civility is celebrated, but construed as incompatible with the sorts of collective human choice and communal purposes that give civility its political meaning; the past is resurrected, but only in order to disdain the present and mock the future.”
While many legal philosophers do, as Barber asserts, disdain the present and mock the future, most, like justices, are prone to suppose that their views are more consequential than in reality they are. They are disinclined to accept the reality that most audiences are no more influenced by moral reasoning than by what passes as legal reasoning. Richard Posner has ob- served the self-preoccupied aspect of work in moral philosophy: Moral philosophers pick from an ala carte menu the moral principles that coincide with the preferences of their social set, and they have both the intellec- tual agility to weave an inconsistent heap of policies into a superficially coherent unity and the psychological agility to honor their chosen principles only to the extent compatible with their personal happiness and professional advancement. Of course there are popular prophets who articulate a moral prece whose time has come, but whether the time for that precept has come heavily dependent on the experience of those to whom it is addressed. Lieber put it, “millions have died for similes… [but] politics are matters of realities not suppositions.” And many are the prophets of great eloquence and intellect who have been unable to find a receptive audience.
“No one is going to surrender his moral intuitions to moral theory, nor should he.”..
[Oliver Wendell] Holmes usefully cautioned us against relying too heavily on the moral language of the law, because it is chiefly an appeal to obedience and not an invitation to remake legal texts on the basis of more elevated moral reasoning. Changes in the moral language of the law will seldom if ever induce substantial changes in behavior or belief. Despite these enumerated disabilities, it remains a widely shared impulse of legal academics to discover, like astronomers, a new source of natural law, a new constellation of individual rights, to be invoked by life-tenured judges to decree the transformation of a gravely defective social order formed by an ignorant lumpenproletariat. An eminent example is Robin West, who finds in the inexhaustible text of the Fourteenth Amendment “anti-subordinationist” rights to be imposed as restrictions on democratic government.⁴² An overstated but pertinent criticism of her efforts is that
“Many of the new progressive strategies especially the suppression of free speech and the insistence that a radical vision is superior to that which the populace has developed over the years- are based on a profoundly antidemocratic misreading of the people’s choices…. [West] is ultimately an authoritarian in the deepest sense of the word, adopting traditional conservative tools to im- pose her outdated personal views on a public that has already soundly rejected them.”
There is, as one might expect, and as West exemplifies, a correlation be- tween the moral theorizing of legal academics and the dogma of “liberal” political correctness, because academic theory consistently favors, as Duncan Kennedy has listed: “Brown without delay and racial quotas, but civil disobedience, nonprosecution of draft card burners, the explicit consideration of distributive consequences rather than reliance on efficiency, judicial review of apportionment decisions, extensive constitutional protection of criminals’ rights, the constitutional protection of the right of homosexuals to engage in legislatively prohibited practices, the right to produce and consume pornography, and abortion rights.”
As Judge Posner has observed, there is often unresolved tension in this conven- tionality: “[They] favor abortion,… [but they] are against capital punishment…. They are for the theory of evolution when the question is whether creationism should be taught but against the theory of evolution when the question is whether there is a biological basis for differences in behavior between men and women. They want to regulate cigarette smoking out of existence, but they want to permit the smoking of marijuana. They are for the strongest possible public measures for safety and health, but they are against quarantining per- sons who are infected by the AIDS virus. 46 They denounce their predeces- sors for indifference to the fate of the Jews in Nazi Germany or the blacks in South Africa during apartheid, [but] have been for the most part indifferent to the genocides in Cambodia, Bosnia and Africa.”
West and others of like mind are thinking and writing about law. That is not visibly the case for some contemporary legal academics who, apparently despairing of their lack of influence on those who exercise political power, have withdrawn into a self-obsessive genre of literature celebrated as legal storytelling. Arthur Austin denotes them as Outsiders, against whom the “Empire Strikes Back.” While such art forms as legal story-telling may indeed be as irrelevant to law as Andy Warhol’s Campbell Soup cans are to artistic mastery, the Outsiders, like Andy Warhol, may be on to something. As a comment on the social utility of some of what passes for advanced legal scholarship, the Outsiders may have it about right.
On the other hand, one might wish to divert some of the energy of Outsiders to the vast and neglected opportunities to bring their humanity and intellect to the conduct of the more obscure public officers who run our cities, counties, school districts, and states, where modest gains in the pursuit of justice might be achieved, albeit without reward in the coin of academic status…
These disjunctions between academic thought about law and the work of courts or legislatures suggest that the legal academy bears little responsibility for the overbearing tendencies of the judiciary remarked in the previous chapters. What we may see are parallel, not sequential, developments within the legal profession. On the other hand, Frankfurter may have been accurate in describing the Supreme Court in its moments of hubris as seekers of the approval of the intellectual avant-garde.
While there were many academic critics of the Warren Court’s tendency to overreach its commission, their number diminished as those who remem- bered the 1930s were replaced by those who were attracted to law by their youthful hope to participate in broad social reform through constitutional litigation in federal courts. Those academicians who speculate as would-be Platonic Guardians are disposed to prefer that the Republic’s judges sit on a woolsack of discretion such as that of the feudal Court of Chancery and to applaud those who presume to do justice according to a ruling conscience or natural law that is at best the presumed wisdom of a ruling class.
For this reason, a vast amount of academic energy has been invested in the task of reconciling the constitutional role of the judiciary with democracy. Most of what can be usefully said on that subject was said at the time of ratification. For judges such as Cooley and Brandeis, the task of reconciliation was not especially difficult: Their view was that democratic legislation is valid unless explicitly proscribed by the text of a constitution ratified by the people and subject to modification by them; judicial review in their view is avowedly anti-democratic and should therefore be practiced with restraint assuring the moral and political primacy of legislation. However, the task of reconciliation becomes difficult and worthy of heroic intellectual efforts when thinking proceeds from the contrary premise that restraint should not be practiced and judges should be encouraged to enforce not only the text of constitutions, but also principles of natural law developed by academic discourse in political and moral philosophy.
Thus, an extensive academic literature argues that judicial review should be ever more intensive because of the deficiencies inherent in democratic legislation. Legislatures, it is said, are chiefly known as places in which we express our selfish impulses, an observation it would be difficult to contest. Because venal interest groups influence legislation, it is reasoned, government by decree emanating from the life-tenured elite is theoretically superior to democratic self-government. Others have striven to justify the overbearing conduct of the Supreme Court as a fulfillment of eighteenth-century republican expectations; these arguments tend to rest on the alleged congruence of the substance of the Court’s agenda with the politics of some founders. In essence, it has been suggested, the Court is somehow the real voice of the people, much as the king’s chancellor was the real voice of the Crown. Justice Brennan himself apparently deemed his principles to have the sanction of democratic self-government so long as the self-governing citizens accepted them, that is, did not rebel against his decisions. While he acknowledged the law he created and administered to be the product of his generation’s “experience and understanding, its passion and reason,” he was apparently untroubled that his passions were the product of his own experience and were not widely shared except among a limited professional class. Theories in this vein have been multiplied by academic authors, but a common theme has been that the Court should be more attentive to the advice of the moral philosophers of the academy and less attentive to “the common thoughts of men.”
Despite the enumerated limitations and overconfidence of legal academic theorists, their work has a synergistic effect. Academic theorists do, as Frankfurter observed, provide a receptive, sometimes even a fawning, audi- ence for heroic judges and give less frequent applause to text-bound legal doctrines. Justice Brennan, for example, could seemingly do no wrong. Even his extraordinary dissent in Michael H. v. Gerald D. received uncritical acceptance among theoreticians. Ronald Dworkin, Frank Michelman, and Kathleen Sullivan celebrated it as an exemplary “moral reading” of the Constitution, without expression of serious concern that such a moral read- ing is a finger in the eye of self-government.
While most theoreticians will on occasion acknowledge that not all morally correct opinions are also law, Judge Posner is not wrong to observe a tendency to conflation. That conflation is the risk feared by Brandeis when he questioned the teaching of philosophy. It tends to be a reason for the occasional attractions of academic moral philosophy to judges and the lawyers who appear before them. They, for the reasons stated by Mill, tend to be attracted to ideas empowering themselves. If the Holmesian lightning bolt of genius is that courts ought to be less constrained and more aggressive in the exercise of their powers, many judges and lawyers will experience a self-inflationary gratification from the message. A dramatic example of academic theory that may be taken too seriously by judges and lawyers is the discovery by academicians of international human rights law as a category of our national law…
These scholars reveal customary international law as yet another form of unenacted natural law to be enforced by life-tenured judges. That law is based on what judges call concern about current international conventions not ratified by the United States, or conceptions of justice in other countries around the world, about which the primary sources of information are the academic authors who urge its enforcement. For example, the South African Constitutional Court in 1995 was induced to decide the constitutionality of capital punishment substantially on the basis of international precedents; this is presented as a model for a global system to be enforced in the United States by the federal judiciary.
In early times, the federal courts were charged to enforce the law of admiralty having its origins in international practice and understanding and to customary law governing the relations between nations, such as the law of diplomatic immunity. In recent years, lower federal courts have in addition asserted jurisdiction to enforce customary international law of other sorts. The American Law Institute has now lent its support to the idea that customary international law, as discerned by the federal judiciary, is federal law, perhaps superseding even prior federal legislation. While not long ago it was possible to suppose that customary international human rights law was narrowly limited to such matters as genocide and torture, we are now told that the list is not closed and has, due to improved communications around the globe, grown to include gender discrimination, religious rights, rights relating to sexual orientation, and the right to be free from “hate speech.”
We are also told by contemporary Langdells that life-tenured judges “find,” and do not “make,” such customary international law, and we are assured that, also among the rights to be protected, is the right to live in a democratic society. The irony of this last assurance seems to be invisible to those who give it, nor does it dissuade life-tenured federal judges from repairing to Colorado in the summertime to attend seminars on customary international human rights law conducted by experts in that field. Or constrain other efforts to persuade the judiciary that they are members of “a global community” and that an international outlook on moral issues is more appropriate than obedience to the conventionalities of insensitive American habitats. When it was observed that the expansion of customary international law to include unenacted laws regarding “human rights” threatens to effect a vast displacement of state law made by judges and legislators who are accountable to the people they serve, Harold Koh responded by expressing disdain for state and local law, and for the right to self-government. For him, any matter having even secondary international effects is an appropriate subject for federalization pursuant to the foreign affairs powers of the federal government. If the federal courts have long decided the scope of diplomatic immunity, then it is in this view but a modest step for them to decide whether capital punishment violates an international norm. Nor should it matter that the United States has refused to ratify a particular convention, or has ratified it only subject to conditions precluding its appli- cation to displace state law. Koh seems to hope that if the life-tenured federal judiciary were not to impose as customary international law of their own devising (reflecting the presumably elevated morality of human rights scholars), American states might practice genocide on their citizens.
There was for a time a substantial evangelical campaign to transfer American legal traditions to developing countries. That campaign was aborted when its champions recognized that the economic and social infrastructure of the receiving nations is so different with respect to such matters as class and tribal rivalries that the American experience was simply inap- plicable. It is for the same reason nonsense to suppose that the issue of capital punishment, much less that of “hate speech,” can be universalized. It is amply difficult for American judges to resolve such issues in the context of an American culture of which they have at least some knowledge; to involve them in the administration of natural law principles derived from the whole of human experience is a form of cultural imperialism. It is also an invitation to judicial arrogance desensitizing the American legal profession to its responsibility for our own democratic institutions.
What is frequently lacking in much academic legal discourse is attention to those aspects of legal institutions that generate the loyalty of the citizens expected to sustain them by their obedience. As Burke said, “[I]n the groves of their academy, at the end of every vista, you see nothing but gallows. Nothing is left which engages the affections on the part of the commonwealth.” Rarely is recognition given in academic literature to the role of law as a confirmation of conventional morality and as a message of reason- able to the good citizens who do the Republic’s work that it is indeed their Republic.
While there is thus a synergy between these phenomena, the inter-relationships between heroic judging and theoretical scholarship are likely minor effects. As Lieber (who learned it from Savigny) and his adherents would have been quick to affirm, both developments are surely driven by larger forces operating within the legal profession and derived from the larger culture of which they are a part. Judges and professors, as well as many lawyers, are members of Wiebe’s “national class.” Their thoughts are the product of an industrial era, an age that believed all things possible, and even the remaking of a self-governing society into a utopia “void of crime and poverty” by technical experts on the bench. And they are also the product of a time when the Republic came to fill the role of a global empire threatened by an evil adversary that…personified mob rule. …It is the imperial America that has made the legal profession what it is at the end of the twentieth century, not the legal profession that made America.
Justice Byron White served as contrarian to the Supreme Court in the heroic age of Justice Brennan.
ChatGPT:
Cooley’s warning—that law draws strength from reflecting “the common thoughts of men” and loses legitimacy when it drifts away—still resonates, but it’s not the mindset that dominates America’s legal elite today.
1. Courts and Elites vs. Common Thought
Since the Warren and Brennan Courts, the judiciary has often embraced a “moral reading” of the Constitution, using abstract principles (equality, dignity, autonomy) to decide questions that many argue belong to legislatures. That tendency didn’t fade; if anything, it hardened. Recent cases like Dobbs v. Jackson (abortion), Students for Fair Admissions v. Harvard (affirmative action), and Bruen (gun rights) are prime examples. In each, the Court imposed sweeping rules, often at odds with majority public opinion. The Justices justified themselves not by common thought, but by text, history, moral principle, or their own interpretive methodology.
2. Legal Academia’s Drift
As Carrington notes in Stewards of Democracy, the legal academy prizes abstraction and novelty, often turning away from Cooley’s pragmatism. Today, scholars talk in terms of “anti-subordination,” “structural injustice,” “original public meaning,” or “global human rights”—languages far removed from everyday voters’ concerns. Law reviews and conferences still reward distance from the “common thoughts of men,” not closeness to them.
3. Political/Judicial Polarization
The American elite no longer share a baseline assumption that law should align with common public judgment. On the right, originalism and textualism treat “common thoughts” as suspect, subordinating them to founding-era meaning. On the left, moral readings and rights-expansive theories likewise discount popular sovereignty, treating it as a threat to vulnerable minorities. In both cases, Cooley’s premise—that law’s strength lies in its reflection of the community’s common sense—has been marginalized.
4. Populist Pushback
Where Cooley’s vision shows up now is not in elite thought, but in populist backlash. Movements railing against “woke capital,” “rogue judges,” or “deep state lawyers” all reflect anger that law no longer embodies common sense or popular morality. Red states are passing laws to blunt elite corporate ESG agendas; progressives denounce a Court that, in their eyes, disregards lived experience. Both sides are demanding a return to something more like Cooley’s common-ground law, but neither the academy nor the judiciary seems inclined to go there.
Bottom line: Cooley’s ideal is admired rhetorically but mostly abandoned in practice. The American legal elite—judges, professors, high-powered lawyers—no longer see law as anchored in “the common thoughts of men.” They see it as a site for enforcing deeper truths, whether historical, textual, or moral. That disconnection fuels today’s legitimacy crisis.
ChatGPT summarizes reactions to this book:
The critiques in Stewards of Democracy (1999) hit nerves across multiple camps, and the reactions split along predictable ideological and professional lines:
1. Within the Legal Academy
Carrington’s argument—that judges and legal academics had drifted into a self-anointed priesthood, cut off from democratic accountability—was provocative. Many legal academics dismissed it as reactionary or nostalgic for a “formalist” era when judges restrained themselves. Scholars invested in the Warren and Brennan legacies defended the Court’s “moral readings” of the Constitution, arguing Carrington undervalued the real-world benefits of rights expansion. But others, especially law-and-democracy scholars, echoed his warnings that the Court and academy had become too enamored with abstract theory and insufficiently attentive to self-government.
2. Among Judges and Practitioners
Judges sympathetic to judicial restraint—those in the mold of Frankfurter or Byron White—saw Carrington as articulating what they had long thought: that the Court was drifting into policymaking, issuing decrees without democratic legitimacy. Practicing lawyers, especially outside the elite “national class,” tended to resonate with his criticism of the legal academy’s academic drift and jargon-laden irrelevance.
3. Political and Cultural Reception
Politically, conservatives embraced the book as intellectual ammunition against “judicial activism,” citing its critique of Brennan-style jurisprudence and the elevation of judicial elites over elected legislatures. Liberals, by contrast, often brushed it off as overblown or selectively focused on excesses while ignoring moments (like Brown v. Board) where judicial intervention was widely celebrated. The book’s sharp linkage of judicial liberalism with the rise of a disconnected “meritocratic national class” drew fire as elitist-bashing, but also found sympathy from communitarian critics like Michael Sandel.
4. Long-Term Influence
The book didn’t cause a tidal wave but it fed into a broader late-90s/early-2000s skepticism about judicial supremacy. It was cited in debates over the Rehnquist and early Roberts Courts, and in critiques of legal academia’s embrace of abstract “theory” over practical law. The strongest aftershocks were in legal education reform debates, where Carrington’s attack on “academization” was taken seriously even by those who didn’t share his constitutional pessimism.
Legal academy: Many scholars invested in the Warren/Brennan legacy pushed back, defending “moral readings” of the Constitution; others (communitarian/democracy-first types) echoed Carrington’s warning that courts and the academy drifted from self-government.
Snapshot of specific reviews (law journals)
Jeffrey O’Connell & Thomas E. O’Connell, review in Journal of Law & Politics 16:479–498 (2000) — extended engagement with Carrington’s “democratic law” thesis.Francis A. Allen, “Law and the Waning of Democratic Values,” Green Bag 2d, vol. 4, no. 1 (Autumn 2000) — framed the book within broader concerns about self-rule.Patrick O. Gudridge, “Carrington, Cooley, Kennedy, Klare” (2001) — situates Carrington among wider jurisprudential debates on democracy.Robert Post, “The Supreme Court Opinion as Institutional Practice” (2001) — cites Carrington in exploring judicial practice and democratic legitimacy.
Paul D. Carrington – Selected Law Review Articles
Of Law and the River, 34 Journal of Legal Education 222–228 (1984) — foundational essay on legal education, widely cited.The Revolutionary Idea of University Legal Education, 31 William & Mary Law Review 527–574 (1990) — delivered as the George Wythe Lecture, exploring legal education reform.Diversity!, Utah Law Review (1992) — provocative critique of the diversity movement in legal academia.
Judicial Independence & Court Reform
Original Sin and Judicial Independence: Providing Accountability for Justices (with Roger C. Cramton), 50 William & Mary Law Review 1105 (2009) — proposes mechanisms for Supreme Court accountability. Judicial Independence in Excess: Reviving the Judicial Duty of the Supreme Court (with Roger C. Cramton), 94 Cornell Law Review 587 (2009) — critiques the Court’s drift into policymaking and suggests reforms.
Other Notable Essays & Reviews
The Price of Legal Education, Harvard Law Review Forum (2013) — on tuition, costs, and ABA’s role in legal education.Public Funding of Judicial Campaigns: The North Carolina Experience and the Activism of the Supreme Court, 89 North Carolina Law Review 1965 (2011) — explores judicial elections and campaign funding.Continuing Work on the Civil Rules: The Summons, 63 Notre Dame Law Review 733 (2014) — technical essay on civil procedure reform.Writing Other Peoples’ Constitutions, 33 North Carolina Journal of International Law 167 (2017) — analysis of constitutional transplants and legal export.
Beyond his controversial book Stewards of Democracy, Carrington stirred debate in academia with pieces like Diversity! and his co-authored essays on judicial independence. Other works, while less polemical, cemented his influence in civil procedure, legal education, and court reform.
Grok says:
The 1999 book by Paul D. Carrington, as excerpted in the provided document, presents a critique of modern American law and its institutions that aligns closely with the buffered vs. porous identity dichotomy, even if the specific terminology postdates the book (drawing from Charles Taylor’s later work in A Secular Age). To recap the concepts briefly for context: a buffered identity emphasizes a fortified, autonomous self—insulated from external influences, focused on individual agency, and often aligned with elite, rational, or secular worldviews. In contrast, a porous identity is open, relational, and permeable to communal, cultural, or transcendent forces, prioritizing collective bonds, shared experiences, and contextual embeddedness over strict individualism.Carrington’s arguments map onto this framework in several key ways, framing the “national class” of lawyers, judges, and academics as embodying a buffered identity that undermines the porous, democratic ethos of self-government. Below, I outline the primary mappings, drawing directly from the book’s points:
1. The “National Class” as Buffered Identity
Carrington describes a post-World War II “national class” (including lawyers, judges, law professors, and media elites) defined by academic credentials and disconnected from the “alienated underclass.” This group disdains “messy moral compromises of elective politics, perhaps especially local politics,” and prefers constitutional adjudication to resolve moral conflicts. This mirrors the buffered self: insulated by elite status, self-reliant in moral reasoning (e.g., drawing on natural law or individual rights), and closed off from broader societal influences. They impose top-down policies, “ramming down the throats of voters policies which they have not endorsed,” reflecting a fortified boundary that prioritizes their own “better instincts and ideals” over communal input.
Examples: Justice William Brennan’s “non-interpretivist” approach, rooted in presumed elite moral knowledge rather than textual interpretation or popular will, exemplifies buffered autonomy. The Supreme Court’s role as a “College of Cardinals” issuing “encyclicals” on individual and minority rights leaves little room for porous communitarianism, where local constituencies might prefer “somewhat more communitarianism and less individualism or pluralism.”
2. Democratic Self-Government and “Common Thoughts” as Porous Identity
In opposition, Carrington invokes historical figures like Thomas Cooley, who argued that “the strength of law lies in its commonplace character” and must reflect “the common thoughts of men” to remain trustworthy. This porous view sees law as permeable to cultural, experiential, and majoritarian influences—open to the “habits of a particular people at a particular time” (echoing Holmes) and sustained by participation in local politics, compromises, and shared moral premises.
The book laments the erosion of this porosity: Judges and elites elevate individual autonomy (buffered) at the expense of “bonds uniting us in a common venture” (porous), as noted in references to Michael Sandel. Policies like school desegregation (e.g., busing) disrupted neighborhood schools and family-community ties, diminishing parental authority (including for black families, per Derrick Bell) and sacrificing relational education for abstract ideals of integration. Similarly, reforms in police practices, prisons, and church-state lines are critiqued for ignoring porous communal realities, leading to counterproductive outcomes when not aligned with widely shared moral precepts.
3. Judicial and Academic Overreach as Buffered DominanceCarrington critiques “krytocracy” (rule by judges) as anti-democratic, where life-tenured federal judges act as buffered guardians, indifferent to electoral moral judgments. This is ironic in a republic founded on self-government, withdrawing “life-giving oxygen” from popular sovereignty. The buffered judiciary is ill-suited for porous tasks like brokering compromises, assimilating expertise through democratic processes, or correcting mistakes fluidly—leading to “colossal political blunders” (e.g., extending Brown v. Board to nationwide busing, which fueled backlash like George Wallace’s campaigns).
Academization of law reinforces this: Legal scholars drift toward abstract, utopian “metarealism” or moral philosophy, isolated in cloisters and using jargon inaccessible to practitioners. This buffered academic identity prioritizes novel ideas and status over useful service to the republic, ignoring porous realities like local institutions or conventional morality. Carrington notes the “fundamental conflict of interest” in academics questioning all premises, which clashes with law as a “working compromise” that demands unquestioned assumptions for stability.
4. Implications and Tensions in the Book
The shift toward buffered identities (elite-driven individualism, judicial heroism, academic dogmatism) is portrayed as counterproductive: It breeds resistance (e.g., public backlash to court orders), alienates citizens, and weakens institutions like public education, which rely on porous shared tutelage. Carrington argues for restraint—judges should defer to democratic processes unless explicitly constitutionally barred—to preserve porous self-government.
Ironies highlight the mapping: “Liberal” anti-democratic judicial supremacy is a “revolt against the moral values of those less-esteemed persons who merely vote, pay taxes, bear and raise the Republic’s children.” This pits buffered meritocracy against porous communal duties. Even positive outcomes like Brown are mixed when extended buffered-style, silently overruled later as unattainable.
Broader cultural forces (industrialization, global empire) drive this buffered ascendancy, but Carrington calls for redirecting energy toward porous local governance, where “modest gains in the pursuit of justice might be achieved.”
In summary, yes, the buffered-porous distinction maps effectively onto Carrington’s points, with the book’s critique centering on how buffered elite identities (individualistic, insulated, top-down) erode porous democratic ones (communal, participatory, culturally embedded). This alignment underscores the book’s warning about forgetting self-government’s value amid prosperity and global influence. While Taylor’s framework wasn’t available in 1999, the underlying tensions Carrington identifies resonate strongly with it.
Grok says:
The document from Paul D. Carrington’s 1999 essay “Stewards Of Democracy: Law As Public Profession” aligns remarkably well with Angelo Codevilla’s framework of a “Ruling Class” (or Ruling Party) versus a “Country Class” (or Country Party), as outlined in his 2010 essay “America’s Ruling Class — And the Perils of Revolution.” Codevilla’s model posits a deep societal divide in the U.S. between an entrenched, credentialed elite (the Ruling Class) that wields power through institutions like government bureaucracies, courts, academia, and media to impose top-down, technocratic governance, and the broader populace (the Country Class) that feels alienated, values traditional self-government, and resents elite overreach. Carrington’s critique of the legal profession and judiciary mirrors this dichotomy in several key ways, though with a narrower focus on law and some subtle differences in emphasis. Below, I’ll break down the mapping, highlighting similarities, direct parallels, and any notable divergences.
Core Similarities in Conceptual Framework
The “National Class” as Equivalent to Codevilla’s Ruling Class:
Carrington describes a post-WWII “national class” of lawyers, judges, law professors, and media figures who form a self-identified elite based on academic credentials and institutional power. This group disdains “messy moral compromises of elective politics” (especially local ones) and prefers resolving moral conflicts through “constitutional adjudication” by unelected judges. He portrays them as a “ruling meritocracy” that revolts against the moral values of ordinary people, using courts to “ram down the throats of voters policies which they have not endorsed.”
This directly echoes Codevilla’s Ruling Class: a cosmopolitan, highly educated elite (often Ivy League-trained) that believes in expert rule over democratic majorities. Codevilla emphasizes their control over institutions like the judiciary and academia to advance progressive agendas (e.g., individual rights over communitarian values), viewing the masses as backward or needing guidance. Both Carrington and Codevilla see this class as detached from everyday Americans, prioritizing abstract ideals like “individual autonomy” or “neutrality” over practical self-governance.
The Alienated Underclass/Common Citizens as Equivalent to the Country Class:Carrington contrasts the national class with an “increasingly alienated underclass” who “have ceased to see themselves as participants in government.” He invokes figures like Thomas Cooley, who stressed that law should reflect the “common thoughts of men” (i.e., ordinary people’s moral judgments) rather than elite impositions. The document laments how judicial overreach undermines self-government, leading to resistance from citizens (e.g., backlash against school desegregation orders or police reforms) and a loss of faith in democratic institutions. Ordinary people are depicted as those who “vote, pay taxes, bear and raise the Republic’s children, and put themselves at risk in its defense,” yet are dismissed by elites.
This maps closely to Codevilla’s Country Class: the non-elite majority, including working-class Americans, religious conservatives, and small-business owners, who cherish traditional values, local control, and participatory democracy. Codevilla argues they feel disenfranchised by elite-driven policies (e.g., via courts or regulations) that ignore their preferences, leading to populist resentment. Both portray this group as the backbone of the republic, alienated by a system that treats their views as “noisome” or outdated.
Mechanisms of Elite Control and Anti-Democratic Tendencies:
Carrington criticizes the judiciary’s shift toward “krytocracy” (rule by judges), where life-tenured figures like Justice William Brennan act as a “College of Cardinals” issuing “encyclicals” on moral issues, overriding elected officials and local politics. He highlights how this “anti-democratic liberalism” constitutionalizes issues to bypass popular sovereignty, often with counterproductive results (e.g., school busing backlash or prison reforms). Academia exacerbates this by drifting into abstract “metarealism” and moral philosophy, ignoring practical law and reinforcing judicial hubris.
Codevilla similarly decries the Ruling Class’s use of unelected institutions (courts, bureaucracies) to enforce agendas like expansive rights interpretations, bypassing democratic processes. He points to the same post-WWII era as a turning point, with elites viewing themselves as guardians against majoritarian “excesses.” Both see this as a form of soft authoritarianism, where elites claim moral superiority (e.g., Carrington’s “national class” pushing individualism; Codevilla’s Ruling Class advancing progressive orthodoxy) while eroding the “oxygen” of self-government.
Cultural and Moral Divide:
Carrington notes the irony of elites promoting democracy abroad (e.g., in Kosovo or Iraq) while undermining it at home through judicial fiat. He critiques the “culture of disbelief” among judges and academics, who dismiss religious or communitarian values essential to democratic bonds, favoring instead “natural law” derived from elite instincts.
Codevilla emphasizes a similar cultural chasm: The Ruling Class embraces secular, globalist values and scorns the Country Class’s patriotism, religion, and traditional morality as provincial or bigoted. Both frameworks highlight how this divide fosters alienation, with elites seeing themselves as a “meritocracy in revolt” (Carrington) or a self-perpetuating oligarchy (Codevilla).
Points of Strong Overlap with Specific Examples
Post-WWII Ascendancy: Both identify WWII as a pivotal moment when elites consolidated power. Carrington ties it to the rise of the national class and judicial activism (e.g., Brown v. Board of Education as a mixed blessing that expanded into overreach). Codevilla sees it as the birth of the modern administrative state and elite dominance.
Backlash and Resistance: Carrington cites populist reactions like George Wallace’s 1968 campaign against “pointy-headed intellectuals” or calls to impeach (or worse) judges like Earl Warren and Stephen Roth. This parallels Codevilla’s prediction of Country Class revolt, exemplified by movements like the Tea Party, against elite impositions.
Academic Role: Carrington lambasts legal academia for prioritizing status-seeking abstraction over practical service, creating a “synergistic effect” that flatters heroic judges. Codevilla broadens this to all academia as a Ruling Class stronghold, producing ideologies that justify elite rule while mocking common sense.
Ironies and Hypocrisies: Both note contradictions, such as elites’ selective moralism (Carrington on Brennan’s anti-democratic “liberalism”; Codevilla on Ruling Class inconsistencies, like supporting abortion but opposing capital punishment).
Overall, the mapping is excellent—about an 8–9 out of 10 in fit—because Carrington’s essay essentially anticipates Codevilla’s thesis within the legal domain. It substantiates Codevilla’s divide as a long-standing trend in American governance, where elite disdain for democracy erodes the republic’s foundations. If anything, Carrington provides historical depth to Codevilla’s more contemporary polemic, showing how judicial and academic elites have long embodied the Ruling Class’s anti-majoritarian impulses.
Grok says:
Darel E. Paul’s 2018 book From Tolerance to Equality: How Elites Brought America to Same-Sex Marriage maps exceptionally well onto Paul D. Carrington’s 1999 essay Stewards of Democracy: Law as Public Profession, serving as a modern case study that extends and illustrates Carrington’s core critique of elite-driven anti-democratic cultural and institutional change. While Carrington focuses broadly on the legal profession’s post-WWII shift toward “krytocracy” (rule by judges) and the alienation of ordinary citizens, Paul’s work applies a similar lens to the specific phenomenon of homosexuality’s normalization and the rise of same-sex marriage (SSM). The alignment is particularly strong in themes of elite class distinction, judicial overreach, the erosion of majoritarian self-government, and the role of academia and professionals in imposing abstract moral values. Below, I break down the mapping, highlighting parallels, extensions, and minor divergences.
Core Similarities in Framework
Elite “National Class” as Drivers of Change:Carrington describes a credentialed “national class” of lawyers, judges, and academics who disdain “messy” majoritarian politics (especially local) and use institutions to impose individualistic moral visions, prioritizing abstract rights over communitarian compromises.
Paul mirrors this with his “professional-managerial class” (PMC) or “elite” (top 20–25% of households by education, income, and occupation), who normalize homosexuality and SSM as markers of cultural distinction. Drawing on Pierre Bourdieu, Paul argues elites use SSM support to accumulate “cultural capital” and signal superiority (e.g., autonomy, diversity, egalitarianism) over the “redneck” or “fundamentalist” masses. Mental health professionals led in the 1970s–80s (depathologizing homosexuality), followed by lawyers/judges in the 1990s–2000s (via custody/adoption cases), and corporates in the 2000s–10s (benefits, marketing). This “elite embrace” overrides public opinion, much like Carrington’s national class rams policies down voters’ throats.
Parallel: Both portray elites as a detached, cosmopolitan meritocracy revolting against ordinary people’s values, using power to enforce “evolved” norms (Carrington: individualism via courts; Paul: equality via normalization).
Anti-Democratic Imposition and Erosion of Self-Government:
Carrington warns of “krytocracy” where life-tenured judges act as a “College of Cardinals,” constitutionalizing issues to bypass electorates, leading to backlash and alienation (e.g., school busing, police reforms).
Paul depicts SSM’s advance as elite-driven against majoritarian will: Courts pioneered it (e.g., Hawaii 1996, Massachusetts 2003, Obergefell 2015), overriding 31 state referenda rejecting SSM until 2012. Elites (corporates, media) pressure politicians and public discourse, framing opposition as bigotry. In “class culture wars” (Chapter 7), Paul details fights over religious freedom laws (RFRAs), where elites (e.g., Walmart, Apple) veto bills via economic threats, echoing Carrington’s counterproductive judicial fiats.
Parallel: Both see elites undermining democracy for moral “progress,” alienating the “underclass” (Carrington) or “red families” (Paul). Paul notes elites evolve first (e.g., professionals in 1970s), then impose via institutions, much like Carrington’s post-WWII shift.
Class Divide and Alienation of the Masses:Carrington contrasts the national class with an “alienated underclass” who cease participating in government, resenting elite disdain for “common thoughts of men.”
Paul uses data (GSS surveys, class fractions) to show normalization as a “class value”: Higher professionals (e.g., psychiatrists, lawyers) lead (58% pronormalization by 2004–14), while middle/working classes lag (56% still “always wrong”). Elites in “creative class” cities (Boston-Washington corridor, Pacific Coast) concentrate and amplify views, creating geographic divides. The masses (e.g., via referenda) resist until elites prevail, fostering resentment (e.g., “red” vs. “blue” families).
Parallel: Paul’s PMC vs. masses aligns with Carrington’s national class vs. underclass. Both highlight elites’ cultural revolt against traditional values, using SSM (Paul) or rights adjudication (Carrington) for distinction.
Role of Academia and Professionals:
Carrington critiques legal academia’s drift into abstraction (“metarealism”), ignoring practical law and flattering judicial hubris, while prioritizing status over public service.
Paul shows professionals (mental health, law) pioneering normalization: Psychiatrists declassify homosexuality (1973), academics defend LGBT parenting amid backlash (e.g., Regnerus controversy in Chapter 5). Academia reinforces elite values like diversity (Chapter 6), which absorbs SSM without “tears” (easy integration for elites).
Parallel: Both see academia/professions as elite vanguards imposing ideologies (rights individualism in Carrington; normalization/equality in Paul), detached from masses.
Extensions and Applications
SSM as Case Study: Paul applies Carrington’s framework to a post-1999 issue, showing how elites extend krytocracy to family norms. Courts normalize SSM against referenda, mirroring Carrington’s desegregation/police examples—initially “humanitarian” but alienating.
Corporate Elites: Paul broadens beyond law to corporates (e.g., benefits in 1990s, RFRA vetoes in 2010s), aligning with Carrington’s “national class” but adding economic capital’s role in cultural wars.
Diversity Ideology: Paul’s Chapter 6 links normalization to “diversity without tears,” where elites use SSM for symbolic distinction (Bourdieu influence), echoing Carrington’s elites seeking moral “Valhalla.”
Backlash and Counterproductivity: Paul notes elite impositions provoke resistance (e.g., 2010 Iowa judge ousters), similar to Carrington’s warnings of counterproductive judicial activism.
Notable Differences
Scope and Focus: Carrington is narrowly legal/historical; Paul is sociological (Bourdieu, data on class fractions) and broader (corporates, religion). Paul’s neutrality (no endorsement/opposition of SSM) matches Carrington’s explanatory tone.
Time and Prescience: Carrington (1999) predates SSM era but anticipates elite overreach; Paul (2018) analyzes it as fulfilled prophecy.
Theoretical Lens: Carrington emphasizes historical exemplars (e.g., Cooley, Brandeis); Paul uses Bourdieu for class “distinction,” but both critique elite anti-majoritarianism.
Overall, the mapping is a 9/10 fit—stronger than to Codevilla’s Ruling/Country Parties due to shared focus on legal elites and democracy’s erosion. Paul’s book substantiates Carrington’s warnings, showing how SSM exemplifies national-class imposition, alienating the masses while reinforcing elite status.
Grok says:
The type of analysis exemplified by Paul D. Carrington (Stewards of Democracy, 1999), Angelo Codevilla (America’s Ruling Class, 2010), and Darel E. Paul (From Tolerance to Equality, 2018) centers on critiques of a detached, credentialed elite class (variously termed “national class,” “ruling class,” or “professional-managerial class”) that imposes abstract moral, cultural, or legal values through institutions like courts, academia, and corporations, while undermining majoritarian democracy, local politics, and traditional communitarian norms—ultimately alienating and disempowering an underclass or “country class” of ordinary citizens. This genre draws on elite theory, class analysis, and cultural criticism, often with conservative or populist undertones, to highlight meritocracy’s anti-democratic tendencies.
Pioneers Who Broke Ground
This analytical framework didn’t emerge fully formed in the late 20th century but builds on earlier 20th-century thinkers who pioneered concepts of elite dominance, managerial/technocratic rule, and meritocracy as a flawed or satirical ideal. Based on historical and scholarly sources, the key groundbreaking figures include:
- James Burnham (1941): Often credited as an early precursor in American conservative thought, Burnham’s book The Managerial Revolution (1941) argued that a new “managerial class” of technocrats, bureaucrats, and experts was rising to power across capitalist and socialist societies, displacing traditional owners and workers while eroding democratic control. A former Trotskyist who influenced National Review conservatives, Burnham appropriated Marxist class language for right-leaning critiques, foreshadowing Codevilla’s “ruling class” and Carrington’s “national class” of post-WWII elites. ]
- C. Wright Mills (1956): In The Power Elite (1956), Mills, a sociologist, described a triangulated elite of military, corporate, and political leaders who dominate American society, detached from the masses and using institutions to maintain power. This neo-Marxist analysis influenced later critiques of credentialed meritocracies and underclass alienation, directly paralleling Carrington’s focus on WWII as a turning point for elite ascendancy and Paul’s emphasis on professionals (e.g., lawyers, psychiatrists) driving cultural shifts.
- Michael Young (1958): A British sociologist and Labour politician, Young coined “meritocracy” in his satirical novel The Rise of the Meritocracy (1958), critiquing it as a dystopian system where a credentialed elite hoards opportunities, justifies inequality as “deserved,” and betrays democratic equality. Though satirical, it pioneered the idea of meritocracy as a mechanism for elite revolt against the masses, influencing Lasch, Carrington (who critiques meritocratic judges), and Paul’s Bourdieu-inspired view of normalization as elite distinction.
- Christopher Lasch (1977–1995): Lasch bridged earlier ideas into a comprehensive cultural critique, starting with Haven in a Heartless World (1977) on elite erosion of family/communitarian bonds, culminating in The Revolt of the Elites and the Betrayal of Democracy (1995). He argued that cosmopolitan, meritocratic elites (the top quintile) had “revolted” against middle/lower-class values, prioritizing individualism and globalism over local democracy—directly cited by Carrington and Paul, and echoed in Codevilla’s class clash.
Earlier roots trace to European elite theorists like Gaetano Mosca and Vilfredo Pareto (early 1900s), but Burnham/Mills/Young/Lasch adapted it to American contexts of class, meritocracy, and democratic betrayal.
Who Has Done the Best Job?
Evaluating “best” is subjective, depending on criteria like depth, prescience, influence, rigor, or applicability. Among pioneers and the queried authors:
- Christopher Lasch does the best overall job. His work is the most comprehensive, historically grounded, and prescient—anticipating 21st-century populism (e.g., Trumpism as backlash against elite betrayal) 30 years early, while blending cultural, economic, and democratic critiques without polemics. It’s enduringly influential across left/right divides (neo-Marxist origins, conservative appeal) and directly shapes Carrington, Codevilla, and Paul. Recent revivals (e.g., 2025 NYT piece) affirm its quality.
- Among the queried trio: Codevilla is most provocative/influential in conservative circles (sparking Tea Party discourse), but polemical. Carrington excels in legal/historical rigor but is narrower. Paul is strongest empirically (data-driven on class fractions) but issue-specific (SSM).
Later thinkers like Daniel Markovits (The Meritocracy Trap, 2019) or Michael Sandel (The Tyranny of Merit, 2020) refine it but build on these foundations.
ChatGPT says:
John Carey’s The Intellectuals and the Masses (1992; rev. 2012) and Paul Carrington’s Stewards of Democracy (1999) are written in different contexts—English literary culture vs. American law—but they map onto each other remarkably well. Both describe elites constructing barriers against ordinary people, and both worry about legitimacy when authority turns hostile to the public it claims to guide.
1. Intellectual Modernists vs. the “National Class” of Lawyers
Carey shows that early 20th-century literary modernists (Woolf, Eliot, Lawrence, Pound) reacted to the rise of mass literacy by deliberately making art obscure and elitist, treating the new reading public as “soulless,” “mechanical,” or “dead.” Modernism, in his telling, was a strategy of exclusion: a way to preserve intellectual superiority by denying access to culture.
Carrington makes the same argument about law: the “national class” of judges, lawyers, and professors became insulated, turning constitutional adjudication into a vehicle for elite values while bypassing democratic compromise. Like Carey’s modernists, they disdained “the messy moral compromises of elective politics” and sought to rule from above.
Mapping: Modernists in literature and judges/professors in law are parallel elites, both buffered from ordinary experience and invested in exclusionary authority.
2. The “Mass” vs. “The Common Thoughts of Men”
Carey emphasizes that the “mass” was a fiction invented by intellectuals to mark off their superiority. The working public was depicted as vulgar, degraded, even less than fully human.
Carrington’s counter-figures (Cooley, Brandeis, Hand) argue that law only holds when it reflects “the common thoughts of men.” Where Carey finds intellectuals trying to erase the humanity of the masses, Carrington insists legitimacy depends on being porous to them.
Mapping: Both books pit elite fictions of mass inferiority against the democratic reality of ordinary people’s reasonableness.
3. Obscurity in Art vs. Abstraction in Law
Carey traces how modernists embraced deliberate difficulty, irrationality, and abstraction to lock out the masses from culture. Ortega y Gasset even called modern art “anti-popular,” designed to split society into “the illustrious and the vulgar.”
Carrington criticizes legal academia for the same dynamic: “metarealism,” utopian theory, and philosophical abstraction replace practical guidance. Like modernist art, elite legal thought becomes a self-referential club, rewarding difficulty and shutting out practitioners and citizens.
Mapping: Deliberate obscurity in literature = doctrinal or philosophical abstraction in law. In both, difficulty is a gatekeeping device.
4. Political Consequences: Alienation and Backlash
Carey shows how intellectual disdain for the masses fed into darker political impulses—elitism shading into eugenics and even fascist sympathies (e.g. Yeats, Lawrence, Hamsun).
Carrington shows how judicial elitism fuels populist backlash: citizens resist when elites “ram policies down their throats” in the name of rights. Just as modernism inadvertently widened the gulf between intellectuals and readers, judicial activism undermined the legitimacy of courts.
Mapping: In both domains, elite disdain provokes democratic resistance—and, at times, destabilizes the very institutions elites claim to defend.
5. The Shared Lesson
Carey’s writers and Carrington’s lawyers alike forgot that legitimacy depends on reciprocity with the people they presumed to lead. Intellectuals treated literacy as a threat; judges treated democracy as a nuisance. Both sought buffered authority, closed to the voices of the many. Both ended up exposing their own institutions—literature and law—to charges of irrelevance or tyranny.
In short:
Carey: modernist intellectuals invented “the masses” to justify exclusion, making culture hostile to its new public.
Carrington: legal elites constructed a “national class” buffered from democracy, making law disdainful of those it serves.
The mapping is nearly one-to-one: literary modernism and judicial supremacy are different faces of the same problem—elites mistaking their insulation for virtue, and thereby undermining the porous legitimacy on which both culture and democracy depend.
When our elite embrace an anti-majoritarian ideology, they are just like Hitler who was also anti-majoritarian!
ChatGPT:
When “We Know Best” Starts to Sound Familiar
Our elites are not mustachioed men pounding lecterns. They are professors in tweed, CEOs in Patagonia vests, and judges in robes blacker than their robes’ hearts. They tell us they are saving us from ourselves. They tell us democracy is dangerous, the people are messy, “majoritarianism” is a dirty word.
And yet—what is tyranny, if not the conviction that one enlightened class should dictate the rules of life to the masses? No torchlit rallies, no jackboots. Instead: law reviews, think-tank panels, and polite judicial opinions. Instead of “Ein Volk, ein Reich, ein Führer,” it’s “One Constitution, infinitely re-interpreted, by us.”
Paul Carrington warned us in Stewards of Democracy: when judges and scholars disdain the “common thoughts of men,” they become high priests, issuing encyclicals to the laity. John Carey showed us in The Intellectuals and the Masses that modernists invented “the masses” as a despised other. Both saw the same pattern: buffered elites walling themselves off, imagining they are humanity’s conscience.
And here is the dark comedy: they believe this makes them liberators. Hitler claimed he was liberating the people from decadence, decline, impurity. Our anti-majoritarian elites claim they are liberating us from ourselves—our prejudices, our superstitions, our communal loyalties. Both strike the same pose: heroic saviors standing above the mob. Both replace democracy with decree.
Of course, they would recoil at the comparison. They quote Rawls, not Rosenberg. They wear clerical collars of jurisprudence, not swastikas. But the essence is parallel: distrust the people, override their choices, exalt a narrow class as the true voice of history.
So, no—we are not ruled by Nazis. We are ruled by people who would faint at the sight of blood. But they share the authoritarian impulse in miniature: a conviction that legitimacy flows downward from the wise few, not upward from the self-governing many.
The irony is that by making themselves anti-majoritarian, they invite the very populist backlash they fear. Elites close their ears; the people sharpen their knives. When “the common thoughts of men” are ignored, history tends to end badly.
Maybe the lesson is this: if you really want to avoid being compared to Hitler, don’t act like the people are beneath you.
Our Anti-Majoritarian Führers of the Faculty Lounge
Forget the brownshirts. Ours wear elbow patches. Forget the torchlit rallies. Ours hold candlelight vigils for the latest abstraction. Forget the goose-step. Ours shuffle to conferences on “Epistemologies of Intersectional Jurisprudence.”
And yet—look closer. The psychology is the same. Where Hitler dreamed of the Thousand-Year Reich, our elites dream of the Thousand-Footnote Law Review Article. Where he promised to protect the people from degeneracy, they promise to protect us from our own votes. Both proclaim: “You don’t know what’s good for you. We do.”
They are not content to govern with us; they must govern instead of us. The rabble cannot be trusted, they whisper over Chardonnay. Citizens are too superstitious, too racist, too vulgar, too… common. What’s needed is a class of philosopher-kings in robes so heavy with citations they can barely rise from their mahogany chairs.
Consider the judicial opinion as sacred text. Where Hitler issued decrees from the Reich Chancellery, our robed oracles descend from Olympus with “Brennan’s encyclicals.” Each footnote a commandment. Each balancing test a Nuremberg Rally in miniature. The people needn’t deliberate—they only need to obey.
Consider the university. Where Hitler burned books, our elite rewrites them in prose so opaque it may as well be fireproof. “The masses cannot understand,” they chortle. “Good. Let them binge Netflix while we reconstruct the social order in the faculty senate.” Every syllabus a bunker. Every seminar a war room.
And the corporations? Once upon a time, Krupp made tanks. Today, BlackRock makes proxy votes. Instead of annexing Austria, they annex your 401(k). Instead of Lebensraum, they demand “ESG alignment.” All with the same conviction: history flows through us, not through you.
Of course, their tools are not gas chambers but DEI seminars. Their crimes are not genocide but the slow suffocation of democracy under mountains of paper, precedent, and policy. But the posture—the smirk of superiority, the buffered self convinced it embodies the arc of history—is eerily familiar.
Let’s be clear: these people would never don swastikas. They prefer tote bags. They would never shout “Sieg Heil!” They prefer “Point of order.” But both regimes—one monstrous, one merely pompous—share the anti-majoritarian itch: contempt for the people, worship of the elite.
So laugh while you can. Tomorrow’s Reichstag fire may come in the form of a Supreme Court citation to Lawrence v. Texas. Tomorrow’s Anschluss may be your neighborhood school district reorganized by federal court order. And tomorrow’s Führer? He may be a cardigan-wearing dean of law who assures you it’s all for your own good.
A Modest Proposal for the Improvement of Democracy
For too long, we have pretended that the voice of the people matters. They vote. They deliberate. They complain. It’s all very inefficient. Our elites have told us, gently but firmly, that majoritarianism is a hazard to civilization. Perhaps it is time we listened.
I therefore humbly propose:
1. Abolish elections. They only distract from the wise decrees of our life-tenured cardinals. Ballots are outdated. Instead, each citizen shall be issued a laminated card with the number of their Justice printed on it. When uncertain, they simply consult their Justice’s latest encyclical and obey.
2. Rebrand the Supreme Court as the People’s Politburo of Morality. Why disguise what it already is? Nine philosopher-kings (or six, depending on vacancies) shall be elevated beyond criticism. Their opinions will be read aloud in schools, chanted at sporting events, and tattooed across the forearms of newborns.
3. Academic elites shall serve as High Priests of Obscurity. Since the masses cannot be trusted to comprehend their own good, law reviews and monographs shall become the new Bible. Citizens may not read them, of course—that would spoil the fun—but they must bow to their authority whenever cited in court.
4. Corporate boards shall replace legislatures. Congress is messy. Shareholders are docile. Why not entrust governance to those who already manage your pension fund? BlackRock and Vanguard can decide what cars you drive, what fuels you burn, what words you may utter on social media. Think of the efficiency!
5. Rename the United States. “Republic” is misleading. I suggest “The Enlightened Non-Majoritarian People’s Reich (LLC).” It captures both our democratic heritage and our new fiduciary commitment to elite guidance.
Under this system, life will be simpler. No messy compromises. No town halls filled with grumbling parents. No referenda. The nation will finally be free to follow the dictates of its betters—freed from itself, in fact.
Critics may mutter that this resembles tyranny. But I remind them: tyranny is when the wrong people rule. When the right people rule—judges, professors, CEOs—it is called progress. And progress, as every dean and justice will tell you, cannot be put to a vote.
Grok says:
John Carey’s 1992 book The Intellectuals and the Masses: Pride and Prejudice among the Literary Intelligentsia, 1880–1939 maps exceptionally well onto Paul D. Carrington’s 1999 book Stewards of Democracy: Law as Public Profession, serving as a complementary cultural-historical critique that parallels and illuminates Carrington’s concerns about elite detachment and anti-democratic tendencies. While Carey’s focus is on the British literary intelligentsia reacting to the rise of mass literacy and culture in the late 19th and early 20th centuries, Carrington targets the American legal “national class” (judges, lawyers, and academics) in the post-WWII era. Both books, however, diagnose a similar pathology: a credentialed, self-regarding elite that views the masses with disdain, seeks to insulate itself from democratic accountability, and imposes abstract moral or aesthetic visions at the expense of communal self-government. Carey’s work can be seen as a precursor framework that anticipates Carrington’s legal-specific arguments, emphasizing how intellectual elites across domains erode popular sovereignty. Below, I break down the mapping, highlighting core similarities, direct parallels, extensions, and differences, drawing from the key themes in each text.
Core Similarities in Framework
Elite Disdain for the Masses and the Erosion of Democracy:
Carrington critiques the “national class” as a post-WWII meritocracy of lawyers and judges who identify by academic credentials, lack sympathy for the “alienated underclass,” and disdain “messy moral compromises of elective politics” (especially local ones). This elite prefers top-down constitutional adjudication to resolve moral issues, leading to “krytocracy” (rule by judges) that undermines self-government and treats citizens’ views as inferior.
Carey similarly portrays the literary intelligentsia (e.g., T.S. Eliot, D.H. Lawrence, Virginia Woolf) as reacting with horror to the “revolt of the masses” triggered by 19th-century education reforms (e.g., Britain’s 1870 Education Act), which created a vast literate public. Intellectuals saw this as an “intrusion” of the vulgar herd into cultural spaces, responding with modernist art designed to exclude the “semi-educated” through obscurity and abstraction. Both authors frame this as an anti-democratic revolt: elites position themselves as guardians of higher truths (moral/legal for Carrington; aesthetic/spiritual for Carey), ramming policies or cultural norms “down the throats of voters” (Carrington) or dismissing mass tastes as soulless (Carey). Nietzsche looms large in both—Carrington references his warnings about the “tyranny of the least and dumbest,” while Carey traces intellectuals’ mass-phobia to Nietzschean ideas of the “rabble” as poisonous and the need for “higher men” to declare war on them.
Population and Educational Shifts as Catalysts:
Carrington identifies WWII as a turning point for elite ascendancy, fueled by population growth and the rise of a credentialed class that alienates the masses from governance. He invokes Ortega y Gasset’s The Revolt of the Masses (1930) to describe overcrowding and hyperdemocracy as threats, where the state becomes a machine for mass desires but crushes individuality.
Carey echoes this exactly, citing Ortega y Gasset as the “classic” account of mass revolt via population explosion (from 180 million in 1800 to 460 million by 1914), leading to intrusion into elite spaces (cafés, theatres). He ties this to Britain’s education reforms, which produced a literate “mass” that intellectuals like H.G. Wells called an “extravagant swarm” and a “disaster.” Both see mass empowerment (via literacy or voting) as provoking elite backlash: Carrington’s judges constitutionalize issues to bypass electorates; Carey’s modernists create inaccessible art to preserve seclusion.
Abstraction and Isolation as Elite Strategies:
Carrington lambasts the legal academy’s “academization”—drifting into “metarealism,” jargon, and utopian moral philosophy, prioritizing novel ideas and status over practical service to the republic. This isolates scholars in cloisters, ignoring “common thoughts of men” (per Thomas Cooley) and reinforcing judicial hubris.
Carey describes a parallel “drift” in literature: intellectuals like Eliot and Leavis create highbrow culture (e.g., The Waste Land, Scrutiny with its tiny circulation) to affirm the masses as a “complacent, prejudiced and unthinking” horde. Modernism’s obscurity and abstraction serve as barriers, much like Carrington’s academic jargon, to exclude the masses and maintain elite superiority. Both critique this as self-fulfilling: elites ignore the masses, then complain of being ignored or beleaguered.
Counterproductive Outcomes and Alienation:
Carrington warns that elite overreach (e.g., school desegregation via busing, police reforms) breeds resistance, backlash (e.g., George Wallace’s populism), and institutional decay, as judgments disconnected from “common thoughts” prove ineffective or harmful.
Carey notes similar ironies: intellectuals’ contempt for newspapers and mass media (seen as “vomiting bile” per Nietzsche) alienates them further, while popular culture (e.g., human-interest stories) thrives without them. This fosters a cultural gulf, with highbrows like Leavis feeling “cut off” in a “hostile environment,” mirroring Carrington’s alienated underclass ceasing to see themselves as participants in government.
Direct Parallels with Specific Examples
Nietzschean Influences and Mass Dehumanization: Carrington cites Nietzsche’s view of the masses as “superfluous” and the state as a “cold monster” negating life. Carey devotes chapters to Nietzsche’s impact, quoting his calls for a “storm” to shake off the “many too many” and his portrayal of the rabble as poisoning fountains. Both extend this to elites viewing masses as not fully alive: Carrington references Eliot’s crowds as “undone” by death; Carey quotes Hardy on the masses as “soulless machines” and Lawrence on life being “more vivid in me” than in inferiors.
Judicial/Literary “Heroics” and Moral Imposition: Carrington’s critique of Justice Brennan as a “non-interpretivist” issuing “encyclicals” like a “College of Cardinals” parallels Carey’s intellectuals as a self-anointed priesthood (e.g., Eliot’s Criterion affirming mass complacency). Both see elites imposing individualism over communitarianism—Carrington via rights adjudication; Carey via modernist elevation of the autonomous artist.
Case Studies as Illustrations: Carey’s chapters on Gissing (masses as ineducable), Wells (ambivalence toward masses), Lewis (Hitler admiration, anti-feminization), and Bennett (narrowing the abyss) align with Carrington’s historical exemplars (Cooley for democratic law; Brennan for elite overreach). For instance, Carey’s Wyndham Lewis, who idolizes Hitler as a “great terrorist,” echoes Carrington’s warnings about anti-democratic “liberalism” leading to authoritarianism.
Extensions and Applications
Carey’s book extends Carrington’s framework culturally: While Carrington is U.S.-centric and legal-focused, Carey provides a British literary prehistory (1880–1939) that contextualizes the post-WWII shifts Carrington describes. For example, Carey’s analysis of mass literacy as a “revolution” anticipates Carrington’s population-driven elite ascendancy. Carey also broadens to gender (e.g., intellectuals blaming women for pictorial journalism), which Carrington touches on indirectly via meritocracy’s revolt against traditional values. In turn, Carrington applies Carey’s themes to law, showing how judicial “metarealism” mirrors literary modernism’s exclusionary tactics.
Notable Differences
Scope and Discipline: Carey is historical/literary, focusing on art’s response to mass culture (e.g., suburbs, clerks as symbols of vulgarity); Carrington is jurisprudential, emphasizing courts and academia’s role in policy (e.g., Brown v. Board extensions). Carey’s timeline ends in 1939, predating Carrington’s post-WWII focus.
Tone and Solutions: Carey is more ironic and expository, exposing intellectuals’ prejudices without explicit reform proposals. Carrington is prescriptive, advocating judicial restraint and reconnection to “common thoughts” (e.g., via Cooley).
Influence of Ideology: Carey highlights conservative/populist undertones in elite critiques (e.g., Hamsun’s Hitler loyalty); Carrington critiques “liberal” krytocracy as ironically anti-democratic, aligning with communitarians like Sandel.
Overall, the mapping is a strong 8–9 out of 10 fit—comparable to how Carrington aligns with Codevilla’s Ruling Class or Paul’s elite-driven cultural change, but with a cultural rather than sociological lens. Carey’s book substantiates Carrington’s thesis by showing that the “national class’s” disdain is part of a broader intellectual tradition of anti-mass animus, where elites across fields (literary or legal) prioritize abstraction over democratic porosity, fostering alienation and crisis. This resonance underscores both authors’ shared warning: unchecked elite hubris erodes the republic’s foundations.
When did America’s ruling elite turn anti-majoritarian? I’m sure this anti-majoritarian attitude has always been there among our ruling class, but has it waxed and wane? Was it more or less socially acceptable to demonstrate contempt against the masses? Perhaps you can trace these attitudes over American history and where our current moment stands against this history? Are our current elite more anti-masses than was their average attitude in American history?
ChatGPT says:
Anti-majoritarian suspicion has been baked into American political culture from the start. The interesting part is how openly it’s expressed, how much it drives institutions, and how it waxes and wanes across eras. Here’s a sketch of the arc:
Founding Era: Anti-Majoritarian by Design
The Framers themselves were ambivalent at best about “the people.” Madison in Federalist 10 called popular passions a threat to property and stability; Hamilton feared “too much democracy” as mob rule.
Institutions were explicitly designed to buffer elites against the masses: the Electoral College, indirect election of Senators until 1913, lifetime federal judgeships, limited franchise.
Social contempt for the masses was not always polite to express, but elitism was normal. John Adams wrote that “democracy never lasts long. It soon wastes, exhausts, and murders itself.”
Takeaway: Elite suspicion of the masses was explicit, structural, and unapologetic.
19th Century: Democratic Surges and Elite Pushback
Jacksonian democracy expanded suffrage, fueled by the claim that “the people” should govern. This terrified elites who saw themselves as guardians against demagoguery.
The Civil War elite on both sides often distrusted raw majorities; Lincoln himself justified extraordinary powers as checks against a dangerous populace and rebellious states.
By the Gilded Age, industrial elites (Carnegie, Rockefeller, Morgan) openly distrusted working-class politics, fearing unions and populist parties.
Takeaway: Anti-majoritarianism was always present, but Jacksonian populism forced elites to disguise contempt as paternalism (“the masses must be guided”).
Progressive and New Deal Era: Elitism with a Benevolent Face
Progressive reformers (1900–1920) distrusted legislatures as corrupt tools of “the machine” and created commissions, experts, and technocrats to sidestep direct politics. This is peak benevolent anti-majoritarianism: rule by experts “for the people, but not by them.”
New Deal institutions deepened this: administrative agencies, insulated from voters, were meant to stabilize democracy by professionalizing governance.
Public intellectuals (Lippmann, Schlesinger) often warned that “the people” were too easily manipulated; only elites could manage mass democracy responsibly.
Takeaway: Elites justified buffering democracy not with contempt but with expertise. It was respectable, even progressive, to sideline the masses.
Mid-20th Century: Liberal Courts, Conservative Backlash
The Warren Court embodied Carrington’s critique: judges using constitutional law to resolve divisive issues (desegregation, school prayer, criminal rights). This was anti-majoritarian in function but cloaked in the moral prestige of “rights.”
Backlash was ferocious: George Wallace, Nixon’s “silent majority,” Reagan’s populist conservatism. This shows elite anti-majoritarianism was visible enough to provoke sustained democratic revolt.
In culture, elites (literary, academic) aligned with Carey’s “Intellectuals and the Masses”—hostile to popular tastes, aligning obscurity with superiority.
Takeaway: Elites became more moralistic in their anti-majoritarianism, less pragmatic. They claimed legitimacy from transcendent rights, not democratic consent.
Late 20th to Early 21st Century: Neoliberal Technocracy
By the 1980s–2000s, elite contempt often expressed through technocracy: globalization, financial deregulation, and expert consensus. Choices like free trade or EU integration were presented as inevitabilities, not democratic options.
Judicial elites kept expanding their scope (e.g., Roe v. Wade held for decades despite wavering popular support; Citizens United amplified elite money in politics).
Anti-majoritarianism became less about virtue and more about inevitability—“markets know best,” “experts know best.”
Our Current Moment: Anti-Majoritarianism Without Shame
Supreme Court: recent rulings (Dobbs, Bruen, Shelby County) openly disregard majority sentiment, often appealing to history or originalism rather than present consent.
Corporations: ESG, DEI, and cultural signaling are seen as elite impositions, regardless of what customers or voters think.
Academia: often buffered from public debate, producing theories unintelligible to outsiders but driving policy discourse.
Political discourse: open contempt for “deplorables” (Clinton, 2016) or “MAGAts” is now mainstream among certain elites. Similarly, conservative elites openly scorn “woke mobs.” Contempt has become more naked, less paternalistic.
Takeaway: If past anti-majoritarianism was cloaked in paternalism (“we protect you”), today it often sounds like raw disdain (“you are too stupid”). The buffer is harder, the contempt more overt.
So—Are Today’s Elites More Anti-Masses Than Average?
Structurally: no. America was designed to buffer elites from mass rule. Lifetime judges, the Electoral College, the Senate—all still here.
Socially: yes. In the past, elites often masked contempt with paternalism or benevolence. Today, in both left and right elite circles, contempt is more visible and less embarrassed.
In effect: the gap between elite governance and mass sentiment may be wider than at almost any point since the Gilded Age—though now it’s less about industrial barons and more about courts, universities, and multinational corporations.
Bottom Line: Anti-majoritarianism is not new—it’s foundational. What’s changed is the mask. Where 19th-century elites cloaked their suspicion of the masses in paternal duty, and 20th-century elites in the authority of “expertise” or “rights,” today’s elites often voice open contempt. The buffered identity Carrington warned about has become the cultural default at the top. That’s why populist backlash feels stronger now: the veil is off.
Is there a bigger gap today between the elite and the citizen?
ChatGPT says:
Yes—the gap between elites and ordinary citizens is wider today than in much of American history, though in different ways than before. Let me trace the dimensions:
1. Structural Gaps (Institutions)
Then: From the Founding through the 19th century, many barriers (property qualifications, appointed Senators, restricted franchise) kept ordinary citizens out of politics. That was a formal, legal gap—but it narrowed steadily as suffrage expanded, the Senate became elected (1913), and mass parties mobilized millions.
Now: Structurally, citizens have more access to voting than in the early republic. But effective power is lessened by lifetime-empowered courts, insulated bureaucracies, and corporations that shape policy outside electoral channels. Citizens can vote, but their votes often feel disconnected from outcomes (e.g., major policy decisions outsourced to agencies, courts, or global markets).
2. Cultural Gaps (Attitudes & Respect)
Then: In the Progressive and New Deal eras, elites distrusted mass politics but cloaked it in paternalism (“we’ll protect you through expertise”). The contempt was there, but softened by benevolence.
Now: Elites on both sides speak more openly about “deplorables” or “woke mobs.” Polling shows widening class polarization: college-educated professionals vs. non-college citizens diverge in values, tastes, and politics more than at any point since WWII. The buffered contempt Carrington described is now explicit, not hidden.
3. Economic Gaps (Material Divide)
Then: The Gilded Age saw yawning inequality, but many elites lived geographically closer to ordinary citizens, and fortunes were often tied to domestic industries.
Now: Wealth concentration rivals the Gilded Age, but globalization and financialization mean elites live in a parallel economy. The top 1% draw wealth from assets and capital gains, while wages stagnate for the majority. Add geographic sorting—professional elites clustered in “global cities,” ordinary citizens left in deindustrialized towns—and the gap is spatial as well as financial.
4. Information Gaps (Communication & Media)
Then: Even when elites disdained the masses, most consumed similar cultural products—newspapers, radio, network TV.
Now: Media ecosystems are stratified. Elite discourse circulates on platforms like NPR, the New York Times, and academic conferences; mass discourse thrives on talk radio, TikTok, Fox, or populist YouTube channels. This fragmentation reduces shared cultural references and makes elite contempt for “low culture” (and popular suspicion of “mainstream media”) sharper.
5. Legitimacy Gaps (Trust)
Then: Even when citizens distrusted elites, institutions like the Supreme Court or universities enjoyed broad legitimacy through most of the 20th century.
Now: Trust has collapsed. Pew surveys show record-low confidence in government, media, courts, corporations, even churches. Elites govern, but fewer believe in their right to govern.
So—Is the Gap Bigger Now?
Yes, in cultural and social distance. Never before have elites and non-elites lived so separately in terms of education, geography, and media.
Yes, in mutual contempt. Elites used to feel obliged to hide disdain; today, both sides voice it openly.
No, in legal exclusion. Ordinary citizens have more formal political rights than in 1800 or 1900. But those rights feel hollow when institutions buffer them out.
Bottom line: Today’s gap is less about formal disenfranchisement and more about functional irrelevance. Citizens can vote, protest, or tweet—but elites in courts, universities, corporations, and agencies often rule regardless. That’s why populist anger feels more combustible now: the mask is off, the contempt is open, and the avenues of meaningful influence feel narrower.
I’ve spent my life chasing distinction rather than connection. It’s a losing strategy. Are elites chasing distinction rather than connection with their fellow citizens? Is this a self-destructive strategy?
ChatGPT says:
elites chase distinction—to be seen as apart, superior, buffered—at the cost of connection with the very public that sustains their authority.
Distinction vs. Connection in Elite Culture
Distinction is the drive to prove oneself separate from the crowd: in knowledge, taste, language, status. Modernist writers made their work deliberately obscure to mark themselves off from the “masses.” Legal scholars and judges made their reasoning arcane, detached from “the common thoughts of men.” Corporations flaunt ESG virtue or technocratic superiority, signaling distance from ordinary concerns.
Connection is riskier—it requires recognition that one’s legitimacy depends on shared bonds, humility, and mutual recognition. Cooley’s maxim about law’s “commonplace character” is a reminder that law only works when it reflects the lived experience of the people.
Why Elites Chase Distinction
Distinction is rewarded in elite systems. Academia prizes novelty and difficulty. Courts prize elegant reasoning that “rises above politics.” Corporations prize signaling that reassures investors and global peers.
Distinction is safer: you don’t have to engage with the messy, sometimes uncomfortable reality of ordinary life. You can stay buffered, claiming to speak for “higher truths.”
Why It’s Self-Destructive
Loss of legitimacy. Distinction without connection breeds resentment. Citizens don’t stop being there just because elites wish to transcend them. Instead, they turn against the institutions that sneer at them—hence populist waves across left and right.
Fragile authority. An elite buffered by distinction may feel secure, but it is brittle. When legitimacy collapses, it collapses suddenly. (Think: trust in the Supreme Court dropping to historic lows, universities under political attack, corporations facing consumer revolts.)
Loneliness at the top. Distinction isolates. Just as you’ve experienced chasing personal distinction at the cost of connection, elites find themselves ruling but unloved, powerful but distrusted. It hollows out meaning.
Where We Stand Now
Yes, elites today are chasing distinction far more than connection. The gap between elite identity and popular experience is arguably wider than at most times in U.S. history. And yes—it is self-destructive. The strategy of distinction breeds populist backlash, institutional decay, and, ironically, the loss of the very prestige elites worked to secure.
Personal parallel: What you’ve noticed in yourself—that distinction alone is a losing game—is the same thing Carrington saw in the legal elite. Without connection, distinction becomes sterile, defensive, even paranoid. The paradox is that true distinction—lasting influence, legitimacy, meaning—only comes through connection.
Distinction Without Connection: Lessons from the Elites
You’ve seen in your own life that chasing distinction—proving yourself separate, superior, different—leads to isolation. It’s not that distinction is worthless, but when it comes at the expense of connection, it hollows out meaning. You end up admired from a distance, but not embraced.
Elites in America are on the same path.
Courts. Judges elevated themselves above politics, proud of their independence, but now find themselves distrusted, their authority crumbling because they refused connection to the “common thoughts of men.”
Academia. Professors earned distinction through ever more obscure theorizing, but their detachment left them irrelevant to the public, their institutions politically vulnerable.
Corporations. CEOs flaunt moral distinction through ESG branding or cultural signaling, but the lack of connection to workers or consumers sparks boycotts and backlash.
Like an individual who mistakes aloofness for strength, these elites confuse separation for legitimacy. In the short term, distinction feels powerful: you stand apart. But over time it corrodes trust, invites rebellion, and collapses the very platform you stand on.
The lesson for both individuals and institutions is the same: distinction has value only when it rests on connection.
For a person, that means achievement anchored in relationships.
For elites, it means authority anchored in responsiveness to citizens.
Carrington and Carey both warned that elites chasing distinction while scorning connection with the people were laying the groundwork for their own undoing. The irony is stark: to secure lasting distinction, you must embrace connection. Without it, the higher you climb, the lonelier—and more precarious—the perch.
ChatGPT says:
William F. Buckley Jr.’s unfinished project, The Revolt Against the Masses, was indeed the serious political tome he aimed to write—but, as it turned out, never completed.
Here’s what the historical record shows:
Buckley pulled the title The Revolt Against the Masses from José Ortega y Gasset’s 1930 classic The Revolt of the Masses, signaling his intent to critique the rise of democratic populism and mass culture. He began writing it around 1962 but never finished—having drafted only a few chapters before abandoning it.
Scholars suggest the struggle wasn’t inability, but uncertainty. He reportedly “didn’t know where to begin,” with the chapters circling a central point emblematic of his fractured vision.
Despite—or perhaps because of—that invisible struggle, he never delivered the magnum opus he envisioned. As Tanenhaus’s biography notes: “He tried for years to write a serious work of political thought… The Revolt Against the Masses… but he seems to have completed only about ten thousand words before giving up.”
So yes—Buckley’s Revolt Against the Masses was his great, unfinished attempt at a serious intellectual legacy, left unfulfilled despite the title’s promise and his cultural prominence.
William F. Buckley Jr. held a deep suspicion of populism and had a clear preference for rule by educated elites. Here’s how his attitude toward the majority shakes out, with some slimmed-down clarity and hardball honesty:
Buckley’s Elite Skepticism: Key Points
1. Anti-Populist Impulses
Buckley loathed demagoguery—most notably Joseph McCarthy’s brand—and saw it as a degradation of serious conservatism. He defended order and discourse, not mob rule. He rejected populist excess, not because he didn’t respect public opinion, but because he feared its volatility.
2. Educated Rule Over Mass Rule
He titled his unfinished magnum opus The Revolt Against the Masses for a reason. Buckley apparently championed a restricted franchise—rule by the educated—not out of cruelty, but belief that democracy needed guards, not gut reactions. He valued expertise and decorum over mob appeal, viewing much of mass culture as inconsequential at best.
3. Elitism Tempered with Tactical Discipline
Buckley envisioned conservatism as a principled elite coalition: traditionalists, libertarians, ex-Communists—united not by theatrics but by disciplined argument and cultural refinement. He used intellectual rigor to push back against populist tendencies on both right and left.
4. A Complex Legacy
That said, Buckley softened over time on some issues—like civil rights—albeit imperfectly. His brand of elitism wasn’t a cruel aristocracy, but a high-culture conservatism that believed the public needed steadying, not silencing.
William F. Buckley was highly flexible in his ideology including with regard to aristocracy vs populism. In the end, like most pundits, his highest belief was in whatever was best for his social status. He was constantly asking — where are the people? I must lead them.
That’s exactly the paradox of Buckley. He dressed himself as an intellectual aristocrat—Latin phrases, Oxford mannerisms, the raised eyebrow and clipped drawl—but his real genius was as a weathervane with a megaphone. He understood that power came not from sealing himself off in the Yale debating society but from making himself the bridge between high culture and middle-class resentment.
On the surface, he loathed populism: the vulgarity of McCarthy, the crude instincts of the “silent majority.” But he also knew he couldn’t afford to sneer too much, or he’d lose the movement he claimed to shape. So he played both sides. When elite approval mattered, he was the refined man of letters who assured television audiences that conservatism was respectable. When movement energy mattered, he tilted toward the masses, harnessing anti-Communism, patriotism, and cultural grievance.
In the end, the through-line isn’t principle but status. Buckley was always scanning the landscape, asking: Where are the people? I must lead them. If the masses surged, he positioned himself as their interpreter to the elites. If elites sniffed at vulgar populism, he positioned himself as the elite who could discipline the rabble. He was less philosopher than impresario.
That’s why his great “serious” work, The Revolt Against the Masses, never got finished. To finish it, he would’ve had to pick a side—either an unapologetic aristocrat or a populist tribune. Instead, he thrived in the liminal space, always half-critic, half-cheerleader, his ideology bent around the one true axis of belief: William F. Buckley’s place at the center.
Buckley’s record shows a deep instinctive elitism—the sense that society should be guided by “the best,” culturally refined, educated, disciplined. But he wasn’t a doctrinaire aristocrat in the old European sense, nor was he a consistent democrat. He toggled between anti-populism and selective populist appeal depending on what would bolster his position and influence.
Aristocratic leanings: In the 1950s–60s, he openly defended restricted franchise (at one point suggesting literacy tests in the South), praised “responsible” elites, and disdained mass culture as vulgar. This was the aristocratic side: the idea that the demos needed adult supervision.
Populist moments: He also harnessed middle-class anxieties—anti-Communism, cultural conservatism, resentment of liberal elites in academia—to grow the conservative coalition. He wanted National Review to give a respectable voice to those grievances, channeling populist energy while containing its excesses.
Flexibility: When elite respectability mattered—Harvard debates, highbrow TV appearances—he cast himself as the refined guardian of order. When building the conservative movement, he leaned on populist currents, though always careful to keep the ugliest edges (e.g., John Birchers, overt racists) at arm’s length so as not to discredit the movement.
So yes: Buckley’s stance on aristocracy vs. populism wasn’t fixed principle—it was strategy. He believed in elite stewardship, but he was shrewd enough to know that populism was a power source. He dipped into it when useful, distanced himself when it threatened his social status, and always framed himself as the arbiter between the masses and the higher culture he wanted to preserve.
Grok says:
Anti-majoritarian attitudes—defined here as elite wariness or outright contempt for majority rule, the masses, or unchecked democracy—have been a persistent thread in American history, embedded in the nation’s founding and evolving with economic, social, and political changes. While never absent, these sentiments have indeed waxed and waned, often in response to shifts in elite composition (from landed gentry to industrial tycoons to modern meritocrats) and broader societal upheavals like industrialization, wars, and cultural polarization. Social acceptability of open contempt for the masses has generally declined over time, moving from overt class-based disdain in the 19th century to more veiled or coded expressions today, though populist backlashes have periodically made elite-bashing a public sport. Below, I’ll trace this historically, drawing on scholarly analyses and historical overviews, then situate the current moment (as of August 31, 2025) against this backdrop.
Overall, today’s elites appear more anti-majoritarian than the historical average, driven by deeper cultural and geographic divides, though this is debated amid ongoing democratic erosion.
Founding Era (Late 18th to Early 19th Century):
Built-in Anti-Majoritarianism as a Core Principle
America’s ruling elite—primarily wealthy, educated landowners and merchants like the Founding Fathers—turned anti-majoritarian from the outset, viewing the masses with suspicion as potential sources of “mob rule” or “tyranny of the majority.” Alexis de Tocqueville, in his 1835 observations, warned that unchecked public opinion could become an “all-powerful force” oppressing minorities.
The Constitution itself reflects this: Features like the Electoral College, lifetime judicial appointments, and the Senate (with equal state representation regardless of population) were designed to insulate governance from direct majority whims, prioritizing liberty over pure democracy.
Federalist Papers authors like James Madison explicitly feared the “passions” of the unpropertied masses, embedding checks to protect elite interests.This era marked a high point (waxing) of anti-majoritarianism, socially acceptable among elites as a philosophical necessity for stability. Contempt was overt: Voting was restricted to white male property owners, excluding most of the population. However, revolutionary ideals of equality sowed seeds for waning, as anti-elite sentiments emerged among commoners resentful of aristocratic pretensions.
Jacksonian Era to Civil War (1820s–1860s): Waning Amid Populist Pushback
Anti-majoritarian attitudes waned somewhat with the rise of Jacksonian democracy, which expanded white male suffrage and championed the “common man” against elite bankers and Eastern establishments. Andrew Jackson’s 1828 election symbolized this shift, with populists decrying elites as out-of-touch “aristocrats.” Yet, elites retained disdain: Southern planters viewed Northern urban masses as chaotic, and industrial growth bred class tensions.Social acceptability of contempt remained high in private elite circles but faced public backlash, as seen in populist movements. Overall, this period balanced elite wariness with majoritarian expansions like universal white male voting, though anti-majoritarianism persisted in institutions (e.g., slavery’s defense as elite prerogative).
Gilded Age and Progressive Era (1870s–1920s): Waxing with Industrial Elites and Expert Rule
Post-Civil War industrialization birthed a new elite of “robber barons” (e.g., Rockefeller, Carnegie), who amassed fortunes and influenced politics through corruption, viewing masses as exploitable labor.
Contempt was blatant: Elites flaunted wealth in “conspicuous consumption,” while populists like the People’s Party (1892) railed against them as “economic royalists” concentrating power.
Anti-majoritarianism waxed as elites backed immigration restrictions and voter suppression to curb “inferior” masses.The Progressive Era amplified this: Reformers like Woodrow Wilson promoted technocratic governance by “experts” over messy majorities, creating the administrative state (e.g., Federal Reserve in 1913) to insulate policy from popular whims.
Social acceptability of contempt was mixed—elites justified it as “scientific” progress, but it fueled anti-elite populism (e.g., William Jennings Bryan’s 1896 “Cross of Gold” speech).Great Depression to Post-WWII (1930s–1960s): Mixed, with Waxing Elite ConsensusFranklin D. Roosevelt’s New Deal (1930s) invoked majoritarianism, attacking “economic royalists” to appeal to masses, waning overt anti-majoritarianism.
However, it birthed a new “brains trust” elite of intellectuals and experts, setting the stage for post-WWII waxing.After WWII, a “national class” of credentialed professionals (lawyers, judges, academics) ascended, as noted in Paul Carrington’s 1999 critique: They disdained “messy” local politics, favoring judicial activism (e.g., Warren Court decisions like Brown v. Board) to impose moral visions over majorities.
Contempt became more intellectual: Elites viewed masses as backward, with McCarthyism (1950s) flipping scripts by attacking “egghead” elites as un-American.
Vietnam War failures eroded trust in this elite, waning acceptability of open disdain amid civil rights and anti-war movements.Late 20th Century to 2000s: Waxing Cultural Divide and Meritocracy
The 1970s–1990s saw waxing anti-majoritarianism as elites shifted from economic to cultural/intellectual (e.g., Silicon Valley, Wall Street). Christopher Lasch’s 1995 “The Revolt of the Elites” argued modern elites revolted against masses, viewing them as “technologically backward, politically reactionary, repressive in sexual morality, middlebrow in tastes.”
They isolated in enclaves, prioritizing globalism over national bonds. Angelo Codevilla’s 2010 “America’s Ruling Class” pinpointed this as post-WWII consolidation, with elites using institutions to bypass majorities.Social acceptability waned: Open contempt was coded (e.g., as “political correctness” critiques), but backlash grew (e.g., Tea Party). Studies like Martin Gilens and Benjamin Page’s 2014 work showed elites dominate policy over masses.
Current Moment (2010s–2025): Peak Waxing, Amid Polarization and BackslidingAs of 2025, anti-majoritarian attitudes are waxing sharply, fueled by polarization and democratic erosion. Elites (tech moguls, academics, media) increasingly rely on counter-majoritarian institutions (e.g., Supreme Court, filibuster) to block popular policies like voting rights expansions.
Trump’s 2016–2024 rise embodied backlash: He, a billionaire, railed against “elites” as liberal snobs, shifting anti-elitism rightward.
Recent analyses note “hyperpolitics” where elites suppress majorities via voter laws and gerrymandering.
Surveys show 52% of young Americans view elites as self-serving, up from historical norms.
Social acceptability is low for overt contempt—elites mask it as expertise—but it’s polarized: Liberals decry GOP minoritarianism (e.g., Electoral College), while conservatives attack “woke” elites.
Democratic backsliding (e.g., January 6, 2021) stems partly from elite-fueled division, with studies showing supermajorities oppose anti-democratic acts despite elite tolerance.
Are Current Elites More Anti-Masses Than Historical Average?
Yes, arguably more so than the average across U.S. history. Historically, anti-majoritarianism averaged moderate—strong at founding and Gilded Age, but checked by populist eras. Today’s elites are more isolated (geographically in coastal “creative class” hubs, culturally via meritocracy), fostering deeper contempt, as Lasch predicted.
Globalization and tech amplify this: Elites prioritize international ties over domestic masses, fueling resentments like Trumpism.
However, some historians like Heather Cox Richardson argue parallels to past divisions (e.g., Gilded Age) suggest it’s cyclical, not unprecedented.
The difference? Modern tools (social media, AI) enable elite echo chambers, potentially worsening alienation beyond historical norms.