Liberals Applauded When Civil Rights Reoriented The Basis Of American Life

Gemini:

Sam Tanenhaus, in his recent biography, Buckley: The Life and the Revolution That Changed America, delves into how civil rights played a pivotal role in shaping and reorienting the basis of American life, especially within the conservative movement led by William F. Buckley Jr. Tanenhaus’s work, including his meticulous research and access to previously unknown archives, reveals that while Buckley Jr. presented himself as an elite intellectual, he also actively participated in and mobilized the “White backlash” vote against the Civil Rights Movement. This, according to Tanenhaus, involved secretly funding segregationist newspapers and White Citizen’s Councils in the South through his family. Tanenhaus highlights that Buckley’s public and private stances on civil rights demonstrate a foundational contradiction that continues to impact American politics today. The Civil Rights Movement, as described by Tanenhaus, was a movement of “deconsolidation”, aiming to dismantle the social and legal segregation prevalent in the country at the time, particularly in the South. This, he argues, forced a re-examination and eventual reorientation of the very fabric of American life and society, revealing a “ghost in the machine” of the conservative movement that continues to haunt American politics.

Grok:

Sam Tanenhaus’s Buckley: The Life and the Revolution That Changed America serves as a mirror image to Christopher Caldwell’s The Age of Entitlement: America Since the Sixties, particularly in their treatments of the Civil Rights Movement and its impact on American conservatism. Caldwell’s The Age of Entitlement argues that the Civil Rights Movement, while aimed at justice, created a new constitutional framework that prioritized race, gender, and sexuality, leading to a sense of alienation among many Americans and fueling a conservative backlash. He sees the movement as a source of division, replacing older constitutional norms with a system that bred resentment and paved the way for figures like Trump. Caldwell frames this as a top-down imposition of reforms that disrupted social stability, emphasizing the costs of these changes over their moral imperatives.

In contrast, Tanenhaus’s biography of William F. Buckley Jr. examines the Civil Rights Movement through the lens of Buckley’s personal and political evolution, portraying it as a force of “deconsolidation” that dismantled segregationist structures, particularly in the South. Tanenhaus highlights Buckley’s early opposition to civil rights, including his 1957 National Review editorial “Why the South Must Prevail”, where he defended white supremacy on cultural grounds, arguing that the “advanced race” should maintain control. Tanenhaus reveals Buckley’s covert support for segregationist causes, such as funding White Citizens’ Councils, which reflects a strategic alignment with the “White backlash” vote. Yet, Tanenhaus also notes Buckley’s later regret for these stances, acknowledging the federal government’s role in enforcing anti-discrimination laws. This shift underscores a tension within Buckley’s conservatism—a “ghost in the machine”—that mirrors the broader conservative movement’s struggle with civil rights.

The “mirror image” lies in their contrasting perspectives: Caldwell critiques the Civil Rights Movement as a disruptive force that birthed a new, divisive order, while Tanenhaus sees it as a necessary upheaval that exposed contradictions in Buckley’s conservatism, forcing a reorientation of American society. Caldwell focuses on the movement’s unintended consequences for national cohesion, while Tanenhaus emphasizes its role in revealing the moral and intellectual inconsistencies within the conservative movement, particularly Buckley’s initial resistance and eventual partial reconciliation. Both narratives address the movement’s profound impact, but Caldwell’s is a broader societal critique, while Tanenhaus’s is grounded in Buckley’s personal and ideological journey, with civil rights as a pivotal influence.

Posted in Civil Rights | Comments Off on Liberals Applauded When Civil Rights Reoriented The Basis Of American Life

What’s the payoff people get from denying the obvious importance of AI?

I love AI. It has profoundly enhanced the quality of my life. I get to explore immediately whatever I am interested in, whether its cosmic ideas or embarrassing feelings. I get to do more work with more accuracy. I create more jokes and more posts and go deeper than I could on my own.

Denying the obvious importance of AI can give people a few short-term psychological and social payoffs:

Preservation of Control: Admitting AI’s growing power can make people feel irrelevant or out of control. Denial helps preserve a sense of superiority or agency.

Status Quo Bias: If you’re invested in traditional systems (academia, law, medicine, etc.), downplaying AI protects your position and justifies avoiding adaptation.

Moral Superiority (this is most AI deniers I know): Some see AI as unethical, soulless, or dangerous. Denial becomes a way to stake out moral high ground—”we’re the humans, we matter more.”

Avoiding Uncertainty: AI’s rise brings massive unknowns. Denying it makes life simpler and less mentally taxing. No need to re-skill, rethink systems, or question institutions.

Group Identity: In some circles, skepticism or cynicism toward AI is a social signal—like loyalty to a tribe. Denial keeps you in good standing with peers who share that view.

But long-term? That payoff turns into irrelevance, missed opportunity, and being blindsided by change you could’ve shaped.

Denying AI’s importance often stems from fear, self-interest, or cognitive bias. Some people gain a sense of control by dismissing transformative tech—admitting its impact can feel like surrendering to an uncertain future. Others, like those in industries AI might disrupt, protect their status quo by downplaying it. There’s also a psychological payoff: skepticism signals intellectual rigor or contrarianism, which can feel rewarding in a world of hype. Plus, some just cling to outdated mental models, unable to process AI’s exponential growth.

People dig in hard because AI challenges deeply held beliefs about work, creativity, and even what it means to be human. It can feel like a personal attack when someone’s worldview is tied to rejecting or embracing it.

Posted in AI | Comments Off on What’s the payoff people get from denying the obvious importance of AI?

Have China, America & Russia Agreed To Divide Up The World Into Spheres Of Influence?

Mark Halperin Monologue Transcript At The 54:14 Mark:

“My reporting has long suggested that almost everything going on now—Greenland, Panama, the trade war, NATO, even Gaza—is about making a big play to pitch to China to carve up the world. This is reminiscent of how, during the imperialist phase around World War II, leaders talked about carving up China like a melon. Trump’s goal is to spend less bandwidth and resources on containing China by saying to them, “You can have some stuff, but leave us our stuff and stop making everything around the globe a big fight.” That’s my understanding of what’s going on, and I see everything through that prism.By the way, that’s why the Japan, Philippines, and Indonesia deals last week were probably even bigger than the EU deal—not in terms of scale and dollars, but huge in strategic importance. You can see every one of these trade deals through the prism of containing China. Everyone.You’ve got people in the administration, including the president, who are students of the past failures of the previous five presidents to figure out how to gain leverage over China to keep them from being on the march, so our grandchildren aren’t all learning Mandarin. Trump has a plan—too many characters, though.I’m not an expert on economic trade policy, but from what I recall, eight years ago, Obama tried to open up the region for us to control by pushing through a trade agreement—the Trans-Pacific Partnership (TPP)—that would have given us leverage over China in the Pan-Pacific. But the problem with TPP was that it favored allies over domestic U.S. economics, similar to a Cold War structure where we allowed Europeans to have economic success at our expense to keep them from going over to the communists.”

Grok says:

Halperin’s claims are partially supported by evidence:Strong Evidence: Trade and defense deals with Japan, the Philippines, and Indonesia are clearly aimed at containing China, and TPP’s structure supports his critique of prioritizing allies over U.S. manufacturing. The failure of past presidents to curb China’s rise is well-documented.
Weak Evidence: The idea that all U.S. geopolitical moves (Greenland, Panama, NATO, Gaza) are part of a grand strategy to negotiate a global division with China lacks direct evidence and remains speculative. While some actions align with countering China, no sources confirm an explicit “carve-up” plan.

ChatGPT says:

Mark Halperin’s claim that recent U.S. trade and geopolitical moves are part of a broader strategy to contain China is supported by expert analysis and reporting.

Council on Foreign Relations (CFR)
CFR notes that the Japan, Philippines, and Indonesia deals are likely less about immediate economics and more about shifting leverage in Asia, isolating China strategically.

South China Morning Post
Analysts suggest these agreements aim to counterbalance China’s economic influence in Southeast Asia, even if the immediate impact is muted.

Economist Intelligence Unit (EIU)
Xu Tianchen argues that the U.S. is pursuing indirect containment through bilateral deals in ASEAN, avoiding direct confrontation while boxing in China.

MarketWatch – Trade Truce and Upcoming Deals
Reports that Trump’s administration structured a blitz of trade agreements ahead of the August 1 tariff reset, aimed at consolidating alliances and avoiding a two-front trade war with China and the rest of the world.

MarketWatch – Country-by-Country Breakdown
Breaks down which nations signed onto trade deals and the strategic implications for U.S.-China rivalry.

Washington Post – Japan Tariff Deal
Details how Japan accepted a 15% tariff in exchange for U.S. investment—less about trade, more about alignment.

The Australian – Strategic Framing
Suggests the White House is prioritizing geopolitical advantage over traditional trade parity in deals with Indo-Pacific partners.

Carnegie Endowment – TPP and Leverage
Contextualizes how Obama’s Trans-Pacific Partnership (TPP) effort tried to box in China via multilateral economic alignment—Trump’s team is doing it through bilateral leverage instead.

Gemini says:

The perspective attributed to Mark Halperin is a comprehensive and internally consistent theory. It interprets U.S. foreign policy not as a series of ad-hoc reactions, but as a calculated, multi-pronged effort to force a new global settlement with China.

Strengths: It ties together many seemingly unrelated policy moves into a single narrative. It correctly identifies the central challenge of U.S. foreign policy (managing the rise of China) and accurately describes the strategic purpose of initiatives like the TPP and modern Indo-Pacific alliances.

Weaknesses: It is highly interpretive and attributes a very high degree of strategic foresight and coordination to an administration that was often described as chaotic. The ultimate goal—a “Grand Bargain” where the U.S. willingly cedes a sphere of influence to China—remains a highly speculative and controversial idea that runs counter to the publicly stated goals of U.S. policymakers across both parties.

In essence, the text presents a classic “realpolitik” interpretation of world events, viewing international relations as a chessboard where great powers maneuver for dominance and ultimately seek a stable equilibrium of power.

Posted in China | Comments Off on Have China, America & Russia Agreed To Divide Up The World Into Spheres Of Influence?

Making Democratic Theory Democratic: Democracy, Law, and Administration after Weber and Kelsen

Here are some highlights from this 2023 book by Stephen Turner and George Mazur:

* The term “administrative state” is now being treated as an invention of the paranoid Right and a misunderstanding of the nature of the state itself.

* The administrative state from its origins has aimed at making public opinion ineffective or undermining its independence, often in the name of leading it, educating it, or providing “justice,” that is to say, something beyond mere “opinion.”

* The administrative state…does not limit itself.

* In the decades after John Rawls’ A Theory of Justice (1971) and especially over the past 20 years or so, many books have been published with the same aim: to vindicate and explicate something that is usually called social democracy on philosophical or social science grounds. After the intense ideological rivalries of the twentieth century, this political ideal has become the default position of virtually all academic thinkers in relevant areas. A century that began with the frank acceptance of the irreconcilability of political value choices, and proceeded with extraordinarily intense ideological warfare, ended with a surprisingly broad, though loose, consensus.

* These writers all reject the idea of freedom as non-interference or choice as inadequate or wrong; they all decry great wealth, the power of money or the power that money gives people, as a form of injustice; and all involve some idea of autonomy governed by reason.

Who are the major thinkers today in the West who deny the great god of “[personal] autonomy governed by reason”?

ChatGPT says:

Most of these thinkers are not centrally concerned with domination in the modern liberal-left sense—i.e., oppression as lack of recognition, microaggressions, or identity-based exclusion. Here’s a breakdown:

  • MacIntyre, Taylor, Sandel
    Some concern with domination, but understood through tradition, community breakdown, and moral fragmentation rather than identity politics.
    Taylor is closest to liberal recognition theory, especially in Multiculturalism and the Politics of Recognition.
    MacIntyre and Sandel care more about the loss of moral language and community than “recognition” per se.
  • Deneen, Milbank, O’Donovan
    Skeptical or critical of the modern focus on domination as identity-based humiliation.
    They worry more about spiritual or metaphysical alienation—how liberalism’s elevation of autonomy fractures tradition, religion, and authority.
    Milbank and O’Donovan explicitly critique modern secular liberalism for replacing theological truth with “recognition” discourse.
  • Scruton
    Opposes the idea that society owes identity affirmation or recognition.
    Emphasizes duty, beauty, sacredness, and the conservation of institutions—not freedom from domination as defined by progressive politics.
  • Manent
    Sees liberal focus on identity as a symptom of moral and political fragmentation.
    Concerned with the loss of shared political purpose, not domination in the recognition-theory sense.

Bottom line:
These thinkers mostly reject the liberal shift toward defining freedom as the absence of domination via misrecognition.
Their critiques aim higher: the spiritual, moral, and metaphysical breakdown behind modern individualism—not the interpersonal slights or systemic marginalizations that dominate current progressive discourse.

Back to Turner & Mazur:

* The right thing is collective; the tension is between the collectively acknowledged good and the distorted private good, which is distorted because it is at heart a quest for something like autonomy and recognition but expresses itself in greed and power seeking, which are the things that need to be collectively controlled.

ChatGPT:

That quote reflects a progressive or Marxian moral-political view: that private desires (like autonomy or recognition) are distortions, and the collective must correct them through control or reeducation.

The thinkers in question reject that paradigm.

  • MacIntyre believes the good is teleological and tradition-based, not a collective imposition on private distortion. He critiques liberal individualism, but not in favor of collective correction—rather, a return to virtues embedded in practices and communities.
  • Sandel and Taylor see selves as socially situated, but not in need of being corrected by the collective. They critique procedural liberalism, not to elevate collectivism, but to recover deeper sources of meaning and moral depth.
  • Deneen would argue that the collective (as structured under liberalism) is the very thing producing distorted private goods. He’s not calling for collective regulation of desire, but for cultural renewal through tradition and virtue.
  • Milbank and O’Donovan reject both private autonomy and secular collective authority. For them, the only legitimate “collective” is the ecclesial body (the Church), not the state or society acting as moral enforcer.
  • Scruton champions traditional institutions and duties, but deeply distrusts any collective effort to “fix” individuals. He believes in cultivation, not coercion.
  • Manent sees the political as a shared moral space, but one that arises from history and religion—not abstract notions of correcting private distortion.

Bottom line:
These thinkers reject the idea that private goods are inherently distorted and need to be overridden by a collectively defined good. They are skeptical of both radical individualism and collectivist moral engineering. Their goal is neither unrestrained autonomy nor collective control—but the recovery of meaning through tradition, virtue, and transcendent sources of order.

Turner and Mazur write:

* There are many other explanations of why “social democracy” has not happened: the media, the pre-existing culture (which is racist, patriarchal, anti-egalitarian, suffused with false beliefs derived from religion, or scientism), a failed public sphere, or other sources.

* They want a social matrix in which the bad effects of competitiveness and striving are tempered, or replaced, by a regime of personal relations in which dignity is respected, autonomy is granted, and people trust each other―a decent society, as Avishai Margalit calls it (1996). All of the “social” goals involve more discretionary power for officials. These authors all embrace the idea of an activist, paternalist, benevolent state. Health care is often the model for the proper role of the state. Where it is done correctly, it combines dignity, compassion, paternalism, efficiency, the proper use of expertise, universalism, respect for autonomy, and sufficient provision with a rational allocation of scarce resources.

ChatGPT says:

Why would a reasonable, decent person object to this vision?

  • 1. It expands discretionary power dangerously.
    The more discretion officials have, the more room there is for bias, coercion, and mission creep. What starts as “benevolent” paternalism can easily morph into soft authoritarianism. Good intentions don’t guarantee just outcomes.
  • 2. It assumes the state can embody moral virtue.
    Critics argue that the state is a blunt instrument. It’s built for enforcing rules, not embodying compassion, dignity, or trust. Trying to make it do so often leads to bureaucratic overreach and unintended consequences.
  • 3. It infantilizes citizens.
    A paternalist state may protect, but it also disempowers. Critics like Hayek or Rieff would say: the more the state manages your moral and social life, the less you develop responsibility, virtue, or independence.
  • 4. It replaces organic trust with engineered dependency.
    Real trust grows in families, associations, and local communities—not by central planning. Making dignity and compassion into functions of state design risks undermining real social fabric.
  • 5. It idealizes health care as a political model.
    Health care is important, but its goals (efficiency + compassion + universalism) don’t translate well to education, family life, religion, or moral development. Many fear a technocratic mindset creeping into areas where it doesn’t belong.
  • 6. It fails to limit itself.
    Once you justify “more state” for one good (like health or dignity), where do you stop? Critics worry this logic gives the state a mandate to do everything in the name of the good, which is inherently dangerous—even if benevolent at first.

Bottom line:
Good people can want dignity, trust, and compassion—and still oppose a paternalist state—because they believe these values flourish better under limits, subsidiarity, and moral traditions that lie outside politics.

Turner and Mazur write: “They err on the side of protecting the culture of the minority group. For the dominant culture, however, matters are different: it needs to be reformed to accord with reason.”

Who are the most eloquent spokesmen on behalf of the majority culture of America, England, Australia and don’t think it needs to be reformed to accord with reason?

ChatGPT says:

Here’s a list of eloquent and influential voices in the U.S., U.K., and Australia who defend the legitimacy and value of the majority culture—without insisting it must be reformed to meet abstract rational ideals or minority-driven frameworks.

They argue that traditions, inherited norms, and majority ways of life deserve respect—not just critique.

Bottom line:
These thinkers argue that the dominant culture isn’t just a power structure to be rationally critiqued—it’s a moral inheritance to be respected. They reject the elite stance that says only minorities need cultural protection, while the majority must justify itself by reason.

Monty Python and the Holy Grail:

King Arthur: (to the peasant) Will you shut up! Will you shut up! [Arthur grabs and shakes him]
Dennis the Peasant: Ah, now we see the violence inherent in the system!
King Arthur: Shut up!
Dennis the Peasant: Oh! Come and see the violence inherent in the system! Help! Help! I’m being repressed!
King Arthur: Bloody peasant!
Dennis the Peasant: Oh, what a giveaway! Did you hear that? Did you hear that, eh? That’s what I’m on about! Did you see him repressing me? You saw him, didn’t you?

Stephen Turner writes:

* Economic power for Ringen seems to be defined simply to mean the influence of business money on political campaigns and lobbying. The fact, for example, that Swedish politics is dominated by a major union confederation which owns a controlling interest in the most important newspaper, is the main force in the party that has ruled with only slight interruptions for decades, and is well represented on government panels is apparently not an instance of economic power for Ringen. If one scaled up its membership to fit the population of the United States, this confederation would be a mind-boggling 66 million strong. This kind of overwhelming power would produce “consensus” even in the United States. Obama, who received the highest vote total in American history, had only 63.25 million votes.

Posted in Democracy | Comments Off on Making Democratic Theory Democratic: Democracy, Law, and Administration after Weber and Kelsen

Trump Uses Allegations Of Anti-Semitism To Protect Whites & Asians From Racial Discrimination

In this deal with Columbia University, it looks like the Trump administration is creating a template for leveraging allegations of anti-semitism to protect asians and whites from racial discrimination from America’s most powerful institutions.

ChatGPT says:

The Trump-era moves—like the Department of Education’s actions against Columbia or Yale—do seem to flip the traditional civil rights script. They’re weaponizing anti-discrimination law not to protect historically marginalized groups, but to challenge diversity policies that supposedly disadvantage white and Asian applicants. And by framing criticisms of Israel as antisemitism, they tie it all together with Title VI enforcement to pressure universities.

It’s a clever, strategic pivot. On the surface, it’s about fairness and equal treatment. But underneath, it’s about dismantling affirmative action and chilling speech on Palestine by exploiting civil rights laws originally designed to protect Black and brown people. The new template turns DEI language inside out—using claims of “reverse discrimination” and “antisemitism” to undercut progressive goals.

Grok says:

The settlement with Columbia, finalized in July 2025, involved the university paying a $221 million fine—$200 million over three years for alleged discriminatory practices and $21 million for antisemitic employment discrimination claims against Jewish faculty. This was in response to the Trump administration’s decision to freeze over $400 million in federal research funding, citing Columbia’s failure to protect Jewish students from harassment, particularly following pro-Palestinian protests after October 2023. The deal restored most of the funding and imposed reforms, including a commitment to end race-based considerations in admissions and hiring, aligning with laws banning affirmative action, and implementing oversight through an independent monitor.

Your hypothesis hinges on the administration’s broader agenda. The settlement does explicitly require Columbia to comply with laws prohibiting racial considerations in admissions and hiring, which could be seen as curbing diversity, equity, and inclusion (DEI) programs that critics argue disadvantage groups like Asians and Whites. Some sources suggest the Trump administration’s Joint Task Force to Combat Anti-Semitism is using antisemitism probes to push a conservative agenda against DEI initiatives more broadly. For instance, a Washington Post article notes that demands made to universities like Harvard included dismantling DEI programs and ensuring “viewpoint diversity,” which critics say targets progressive campus cultures. A post on X also frames the Columbia deal as a model for forcing universities to stop discriminating against Whites and Asians under the guise of addressing antisemitism.

However, the evidence isn’t conclusive that this is a deliberate template to prioritize Asians and Whites specifically. The administration’s public focus has been heavily on antisemitism, with Education Secretary Linda McMahon emphasizing accountability for “antisemitic discrimination and harassment.” The settlement’s terms, like adopting the IHRA definition of antisemitism and enhancing campus security, center on Jewish student protections. Critics, including some Jewish leaders, argue that dismantling DEI programs might not address antisemitism and could weaken broader anti-discrimination efforts, potentially creating a “can’t win” situation for universities under Title VI of the Civil Rights Act.

The edgy angle here is that the antisemitism crackdown could be a Trojan horse for dismantling DEI frameworks, which some conservatives view as discriminatory against non-minority groups. A City Journal piece explicitly argues that the Columbia approach should be expanded to combat “racialism” across universities, citing discrimination against Whites and Asians as a key issue. Yet, Columbia’s public statements avoid acknowledging specific White House claims about reviewing international student admissions or Middle East programs, suggesting a gap between the administration’s rhetoric and the university’s interpretation of the deal.

On the flip side, the focus on antisemitism might not be a pretext at all—it could genuinely reflect the administration’s priorities, driven by high-profile campus unrest and pressure from pro-Israel groups. The settlement’s reforms, like mask bans and oversight of Middle East studies, align with demands to curb pro-Palestinian activism, which the administration links to antisemitism. The risk for Columbia in agreeing to these terms is lending legitimacy to a strategy of using federal funding as leverage, which could chill academic freedom or diversity efforts without necessarily protecting Asians or Whites directly.

So, is this a template to protect Asians and Whites? Possibly, but only indirectly. The deal’s legal and policy changes could limit DEI practices that some argue disadvantage these groups, but the primary driver appears to be antisemitism allegations, with broader conservative goals piggybacking on that framework. Without more explicit evidence of intent to center Asians and Whites, it’s a plausible but speculative leap. The administration’s leverage—using federal funding to force compliance—does set a precedent that could be applied to other universities, as seen with threats to Harvard and others.

Posted in America | Comments Off on Trump Uses Allegations Of Anti-Semitism To Protect Whites & Asians From Racial Discrimination