Stewards Of Democracy: Law As Public Profession (1999)

Law professor Paul D. Carrington wrote:

The concept of a “liberal” krytocracy — one fired by a desire to transform the social order it governs — may have unique at the time of its advent in post-World War II, post-Brown America.

Perhaps the leading twentieth-century practitioner of constitutional law-making in disregard of the rights of citizens to govern themselves was William Brennan… [T]he inflated sense of the Court’s role he seems to be have brought to its work helped to make the Court to resemble a College of Cardinals telling members of the faith what to believe and how to live. The Brennan “encyclicals” required the community to respect a broad range of individual and minority rights, and left little discretion to local congregations or constituencies to believe, or to act upon the belief, that somewhat more communitarianism and less individualism or pluralism might be preferable. The encyclicals were not presented as serious interpretations of a written legal text, but were rooted in natural law sanctioned by reference to the indeterminate text of the Fourteenth Amendment and to what Justice Brennan presumed to be the better instincts and ideals of the people. He was fairly said to be a non-interpretivist engaged in “a search for political-moral knowledge, for answers to the various questions as to how we, the polity, should live our public, collective life, or life in common” and sometimes our not so public life, too. Unlike Cooley or Brandeis, Brennan seldom if ever gave weight to the political judgment of elected officers, perhaps especially those elected at state or local levels. Frankfurter only somewhat unjustly described the Brennan Court as animated by “self-willed, self-righteous power lust.” Whether lustful or not, the Court embraced the belief that anything a legislature could do, it could do better.

There is irony in the denotation of this anti-democratic restoration of judicial supremacy as “liberal,” a sort of code word for the moral preferences of the recently emerged “national class.” As Christopher Lasch explained the irony, many ruling meritocrats revolted against the moral values of those less-esteemed persons who merely vote, pay taxes, bear and raise the Republic’s children, and put themselves at risk in its defense. A visible means of avoiding the noisome duty of persuading these lesser persons of the correct world view was to constitutionalize political issues that would otherwise be subjects of popular governance. The meritocracy in revolt may, if Lasch is correct, have supplied the receptive audience needed to induce high court judges to discard the caution advocated by earlier “liberals” favoring the right to self-government. Indeed, Frankfurter despised that his colleagues were determined to be immortalized in “the Valhalla of liberty” and “in the meantime to have the avant-gard of the Yale Law School…praise them.”

A different interpretation is that of Michael Sandel, who blames the Supreme Court for displacing the earlier American tradition of shared power with a new vision of “freedom” elevating individual autonomy and governmental neutrality at the expense of the bonds uniting us in a common venture. men venture. Evidence to support his hypothesis can be found not only in the conduct of the Court, but also in legal scholarship disregarding the possibility that life-tenured judges ought to or could be influenced in the formulation of doctrine by “the common thoughts of men” or other communitarian concerns, expressing wonder that anyone should be concerned about the Court’s “anti-majoritarianism” and dismissing the concern as platitudinous.

Whatever the social-psychological origins of this anti-democratic “liberalism,” it called into question the validity and integrity of the traditional political rhetoric of the Republic. Life-tenured judges are not in any useful sense “we, the people,” however much one might wish to believe otherwise. To speak of krytocracy as a government of or by the people is a transparent fraud on citizens’ political rights. While none can deny, as Justice Robert Jackson affirmed, that the “very purpose” of constitutions is
“to withdraw certain subjects from the vicissitudes of political controversy,” when “certain subjects” include many or most of those of greatest interest to citizens, the effect, as he noted, is to withdraw the life-giving oxygen from the air sustaining self-government.

As we have seen, our exemplars were mindful of at least three grave problems inherent in political rule by judges. First, as Cooley’s message at Harvard reflected, they believed that a judiciary disregarding the “common thoughts of men” will be resisted by those whose thoughts it disdains. In this view, people do not change their minds, and often not even their behavior, because of the utterances of senior citizens in black robes, especially if they are imbued with the individualist spirit of Protestantism. Judgments of high courts purporting to effect social change are therefore often useless and sometimes counterproductive. On the other hand, Cooley and his successors supposed that people will more readily adapt to policies debated and decided by democratic methods in which they participated, especially if their dissenting views have been prudently accommodated. Second, my exemplars recognized that judges as a class are not selected for their political and moral wisdom, nor is there reason or experience to suggest that they acquire it in office. “Wayward” as Hand observed the vagaries of popular assemblies” to be, judges of all political persuasions are capable of equally colossal political blunders. There are at least three reasons for this. One is that the judicial process is not well suited to the presentation and assimilation of political wisdom. The Brandeis brief to the contrary notwithstanding, legislatures and administrative rulemakers are, as Freund observed, structurally more adept at “mastering statistics and economics,” as Holmes prescribed, because they have direct access to technical expertise as well as to popular estimates of such expertise and have no obligation to address an imminent dispute when they have well-founded doubt about the right solution. A second reason, as Freund emphasized, is that the judiciary can seldom broker prudent compromise between competing values, and compromise is more often than not the wisest policy. That “the best is the enemy of the good” is an adverse comment on much judicial policymaking. A third reason is that the doctrine of precedent to which American courts are necessarily committed dictates that they cannot readily correct their policymaking mistakes. Having written, the judicial hand moves on. For all these reasons, political blunders by the judiciary may be more likely and more costly, even though they are more likely to bear the marks of principled decisionmaking…

The efforts of judges to transform the social order without the general moral support of the citizens are not very effective and are often counterproductive…

After Brown, it seemed that every beleaguered individual group in America, including perhaps some beleaguered only in their own perceptions, fancied that the court in its anti-democratic role might relieve their distress. The idea of popular sovereignty came to be viewed by many American lawyers…as a mere impediment to social reform. And the role of the federal judiciary became once again redolent of the overbearing and pretentious role of the chancellor wielding power in the name of the king’s conscience…

While Brown stands as the shining example of the good deeds that politically animated, life-tenured judges may on occasion perform when their decisions are congruent with widely shared moral precepts, even the Court’s performance with respect to racial segregation is mixed and can be said at times to manifest misuse of its political power. When the Court at last ordered lower federal courts to reorganize and manage the public schools, and not merely in the South where segregation was de jure, it pitted its authority broadly against self-government in communities spread across the continent…

The spirit of Southern rednecks who wanted to impeach Earl Warren was nationalized in the politics of George Wallace, the angry governor of Alabama, who by denouncing the “pointy-headed intellectuals” marshaled a huge vote in the 1968 Democratic primaries in northern states. Many individual federal judges were subject to strenuous efforts to intimidate them; numerous Michigan bumper stickers called not for the impeachment, but the assassination, of Judge Stephen Roth for ordering bussed integration of all the schools in metropolitan Detroit, one of many cities in which school populations reflected segregated housing patterns caused in minor part by historic misuses of local political power reflecting racist impulses. That extremely hostile reaction was most visible in the westside suburbs, which were populated by the offspring of twentieth-century immigrants from eastern Europe who bore no responsibility for historic harms and who perceived no reason why their children should bear the burden and inconvenience of desegregating African-American children for sins they did not commit. Judge Roth, himself an immigrant, was likely responding in his order to the evidence that the burden of desegregation, if limited to the city of Detroit, would fall entirely on those least responsible for it and leave free of any inconvenience the monied, “national” class residing in Grosse Pointe and Bloomfield Hills. While an appeal from his order was pending, he died of a heart attack, quite possibly caused by the stress associated with the odium attached to his decision.

The effect outside the South was to uproot neighborhood schools in black neighborhoods as well as white. Sacrificed in the effort to promote racial integration was the traditional relationship between public education and the family. Derrick Bell, made the point that it was not merely white parents, but also black, whose responsibility and authority over the education of their children was diminished. There is even reason to suspect that the psychological justifications for desegregation were harmfully
self-fulfilling, perhaps even foreseeably so. While it would be unjust to suggest that there was a clearly superior approach to the achievement of public school desegregation or to blame the Court for the poor estate of public education in America at the century’s end, Brown II and its progeny surely made a contribution to the demise of public schools. And, over the longer term, public education as a means by which citizens share the tutelage of their children may be more vital to the Republic than the Constitution itself. On that account, the federal courts have substantially but belatedly abandoned the goal of racial integration of school children as one that is both unattainable and counterproductive. In the extensions of its application, Brown II has indeed been silently overruled.

School desegregation was the defining moment for the “liberal” Court and profession, but it was only a point of departure. With equally high purpose, the Court soon undertook by judicial decree to transform other aspects of American society. Near the top of the agenda was the transformation of state and local police…

The Court in 1964 went beyond its moral and political support in regulating police conduct. In a pivotal case, it held that the Fourteenth Amendment prohibited a state from using a confession secured by questioning conducted before the accused consulted his counsel. And, a year later, it held that the state must advise the accused of his right to counsel before questioning, else a conviction based in part on his confession must be reversed. These decisions were not well-received by those whose obedience was required, for at least three reasons. First, they appeared to require radical change in the customary practices of local police departments everywhere. Second, they coincided with a precipitous increase in violent crime in most American cities. Third, they resulted in the release of persons, many or most of whom were almost certainly guilty of serious crime…

The Court also undertook the reformation of state prisons. There can be no doubt of the squalid conditions of many of them, but whether judges run materially more humane prisons than wardens remains open to debate…

Justice Brennan in his retirement cheerfully forecast that “one day the Court will outlaw the death penalty. Permanently.” It seems never to have occurred to him that the abolition of capital punishment is properly a task for those who write and amend the constitutions and laws of the states and not for his College of Cardinals to decide without regard for citizens’ rights to self-government…

Among the most lawless of Justice Brennan’s opinions was his decision to savage by subtle means the popular institution of the right to jury trial in civil cases…

There is no principle of natural law by which the line between church and state can be judged. While justices may suppose that “the dissemination of science” is a “sufficient agent” of civic moral education to sustain a community capable of self-government, theirs is a “culture of disbelief.” The contrary belief of the Founders that religious life is needed to sustain the ties of community essential to democratic government is another that has not been falsified…

The new age of judicial heroics tracked the advent of the legal academy… Felix Frankfurter declared… “law and lawyers are what the law schools make them.” …industrialization creating Americans’ appetite for technical competence certified by academic credentials…

Since [1900], the legal academy has been drifting into the academic profession and away from the legal profession… The academic profession in America has at least since 1950 outranked the legal profession in social status, to those preoccupied with affect, the doctorate in philosophy in any discipline is a more luminous achievement than a mere law degree and license…

Academization threatens the very benefits it confers by reducing the prospect that studious authors will be taken seriously by those bearing public responsibility. If Holmes’s lightning of genius should strike a law professor today, it is unlikely that “the real world” would notice. The reasons for this are enumerated below. First, academic lawyers achieve status within their profession less by performing useful service to the Republic than by meeting conventional academic standards requiring the utterance of novel ideas pitched to a high level of abstraction. “The remoter and more general aspects of the law are those which give it universal interest,” Holmes said. In pursuing what seem to be issues of universal dimension, academicians tend to forego study of those lesser ones that they might be able to solve and on which public officers are likely to accept their counsel. The tendency to engage in cosmology, or what Linda Mullenix has denoted as “metarealism,” is likely reinforced by the increase in the number of law teachers holding doctorates in other more esteemed disciplines. Ironically, metarealism, even in the extreme form of nihilism denying the integrity of legal texts, is in post-modern diction often denoted as “pragmatism. Yet, as Charles Collier noted, there is very little legal scholarship today resembling three prosaic articles appearing together in an early issue of the Harvard Law Review: Brandeis and Warren, “The Law of Ponds”; Beale, “Tickets”; or Williston, “Successive Promises of the Same Performance.” Instead, legal scholars are prone to exhibit their mastery of almost any other discipline than law.

Second, most large legal ideas were entertained in the time of Justinian, if not even in the time of Hammurabi. There are no new continents of law to explore. Academic lawyers are in this respect in an unfortunate position not unlike that of gross anatomists, who have no hope of discovering a new organ in the human body and are therefore scorned by their medical re- search colleagues who have large mysteries to pierce and whose literature may achieve seeming miracles. This appears to be the realization expressed by Holmes when he quit academic life for the bench. Third, as Cooley remarked at Harvard, and as Cicero and Thucydides had previously observed, sound, useful legal ideas are generally conven- tional ones. So even Holmes conceded that law must respect “the habits of a particular people at a particular time.” “The life of the law is not logic, but experience,” he said in his most famous utterance. Good law expresses the culture of which it is a part and is therefore confined by the moral premises of that culture.

Ernst Freund made the point that: “It is not possible to work a [legal] system successfully if its fundamental justifi- cation is constantly questioned; or putting it the other way, a great system that has established itself will convert its disciples from skeptics into votaries, or will quickly get rid of them. Law, like other human institutions, is a working compromise, and the very fact that it is an appeal to reason demands assump- tions that must not be too closely questioned.”

This reality is odious to academicians of pure heart who regard it as their duty and their privilege to question all the premises of the social order. In this respect, there is a fundamental, but seldom noted, conflict of interest in academic law. Fourth, cloistered scholars are physically isolated from the universe in which real decisions are made. Sound moral judgment on public issues is an attribute not easily acquired within the academic cloister. To be useful advisers and critics to those exercising public responsibility, legal scholars would need to involve themselves in active politics to a degree that few do. Thus, in 1896 Woodrow Wilson, then president of Princeton University, deplored the tendency of professional academics to treat texts as “material” and “not life”; they do not, he said, reflect, so much as “they set forth schemes, [and] expound with dispassionate method.” “Their minds,” he perceived, “are not stages, but museums; nothing is done there, but very curious and valuable collections are kept there.”

Fifth, for reasons implicit in the foregoing observations, the academic enterprise encourages utopian dogmatization. It does not reward the practice of moral compromise, which…is the objective of democratic policies and law. The complex constitutional structure of the Republic was designed precisely to prevent the political implementation of dogma, to compel compromise… Utopianism in the academy has been reinforced by the tendency of the heroic judiciary to perform the role of Cardinals willing to issue decrees to effect all manner of benign results.

Sixth, public decisions…are reactive to immediacies… Even judges and lawyers sympathetic to positions taken by academics infrequently have time or energy to consult academic literature with the care required by turgid academic prose.

Seventh, academic authors are often disinclined to accept the modest role…as mere secondary authorities… To write such work [as 1883’s A Treatise on the Constitutional Limitations Which Rest upon the Legislative Power of the States of the American Union by Thomas M. Cooley], authors must eschew novel thoughts and to that extent disavow not only academic status seeking but the more immediate satisfactions of self-expression…

Eighth, work on intellectual frontiers…often employs the professional jargon of another academic discipline, a jargon likely to impede, if it does not prevent, comprehension by judges and practicing lawyers… The university law school is increasingly a colonial outpost of the graduate school. A self-respecting law school serving the “national class” would be ashamed not to have on its faculty a broad sampling of scholars whose in- terests in law is incidental to a primary intellectual interest in another more academically respectable field, an interest certified by a doctorate in that field. Their work is often difficult to communicate effectively to persons outside the pertinent intellectual community.

Ninth, academic status is seldom acquired by work on the law and politics of local institutions. For the most respected academic lawyers, only the federal government or the international order is worthy of study. Work of the sort done by Freund with state and local governments is out of fashion because it does not command the attention and admiration of the “national class.”

These enumerated circumstances have an aspect of self-fulfilling proph- ecy. Teachers and writers who do not expect a hearing from those in power and not to invest themselves in the effort to address the nonexistent audience in ways that would be helpful to it. As a consequence, …much that now passes for scholarship by law professors is not written with an expectation that it might be read and used by those having public responsibility, with whom academic authors find little or no common ground. It is often discourse addressed to small audiences of specialized academic readers having little involvement in the immediate cares of the world. Academic lawyers therefore frequently achieve the fate of being ignored by those whom they ignore. Indeed, it may be questioned whether many legal academics are still lawyers or instead have become political philosophers. As such, they may be subject to the complaint made against some of the most eminent members of that esteemed discipline by Benjamin Barber:

“They have served the ideal of the enlightenment better than they have informed our political judgment. In substituting reason for common sense, they have declared the sense of commoners to be nonsense. Rights are philosophically vindicated, but only as abstractions that undermine democratic communities that breathe life into rights; justice is given an unimpeachable credential in epistemology, but no firm hold on action or on the deliberative process from which political action stems; talk is revivified as the heart of the political process and then recommended to citizens, but in a form that answers to constraints not of citizenship but of philosophy; civility is celebrated, but construed as incompatible with the sorts of collective human choice and communal purposes that give civility its political meaning; the past is resurrected, but only in order to disdain the present and mock the future.”

While many legal philosophers do, as Barber asserts, disdain the present and mock the future, most, like justices, are prone to suppose that their views are more consequential than in reality they are. They are disinclined to accept the reality that most audiences are no more influenced by moral reasoning than by what passes as legal reasoning. Richard Posner has ob- served the self-preoccupied aspect of work in moral philosophy: Moral philosophers pick from an ala carte menu the moral principles that coincide with the preferences of their social set, and they have both the intellec- tual agility to weave an inconsistent heap of policies into a superficially coherent unity and the psychological agility to honor their chosen principles only to the extent compatible with their personal happiness and professional advancement. Of course there are popular prophets who articulate a moral prece whose time has come, but whether the time for that precept has come heavily dependent on the experience of those to whom it is addressed. Lieber put it, “millions have died for similes… [but] politics are matters of realities not suppositions.” And many are the prophets of great eloquence and intellect who have been unable to find a receptive audience.

“No one is going to surrender his moral intuitions to moral theory, nor should he.”..

[Oliver Wendell] Holmes usefully cautioned us against relying too heavily on the moral language of the law, because it is chiefly an appeal to obedience and not an invitation to remake legal texts on the basis of more elevated moral reasoning. Changes in the moral language of the law will seldom if ever induce substantial changes in behavior or belief. Despite these enumerated disabilities, it remains a widely shared impulse of legal academics to discover, like astronomers, a new source of natural law, a new constellation of individual rights, to be invoked by life-tenured judges to decree the transformation of a gravely defective social order formed by an ignorant lumpenproletariat. An eminent example is Robin West, who finds in the inexhaustible text of the Fourteenth Amendment “anti-subordinationist” rights to be imposed as restrictions on democratic government.⁴² An overstated but pertinent criticism of her efforts is that

“Many of the new progressive strategies especially the suppression of free speech and the insistence that a radical vision is superior to that which the populace has developed over the years- are based on a profoundly antidemocratic misreading of the people’s choices…. [West] is ultimately an authoritarian in the deepest sense of the word, adopting traditional conservative tools to im- pose her outdated personal views on a public that has already soundly rejected them.”

There is, as one might expect, and as West exemplifies, a correlation be- tween the moral theorizing of legal academics and the dogma of “liberal” political correctness, because academic theory consistently favors, as Duncan Kennedy has listed: “Brown without delay and racial quotas, but civil disobedience, nonprosecution of draft card burners, the explicit consideration of distributive consequences rather than reliance on efficiency, judicial review of apportionment decisions, extensive constitutional protection of criminals’ rights, the constitutional protection of the right of homosexuals to engage in legislatively prohibited practices, the right to produce and consume pornography, and abortion rights.”

As Judge Posner has observed, there is often unresolved tension in this conven- tionality: “[They] favor abortion,… [but they] are against capital punishment…. They are for the theory of evolution when the question is whether creationism should be taught but against the theory of evolution when the question is whether there is a biological basis for differences in behavior between men and women. They want to regulate cigarette smoking out of existence, but they want to permit the smoking of marijuana. They are for the strongest possible public measures for safety and health, but they are against quarantining per- sons who are infected by the AIDS virus. 46 They denounce their predeces- sors for indifference to the fate of the Jews in Nazi Germany or the blacks in South Africa during apartheid, [but] have been for the most part indifferent to the genocides in Cambodia, Bosnia and Africa.”

West and others of like mind are thinking and writing about law. That is not visibly the case for some contemporary legal academics who, apparently despairing of their lack of influence on those who exercise political power, have withdrawn into a self-obsessive genre of literature celebrated as legal storytelling. Arthur Austin denotes them as Outsiders, against whom the “Empire Strikes Back.” While such art forms as legal story-telling may indeed be as irrelevant to law as Andy Warhol’s Campbell Soup cans are to artistic mastery, the Outsiders, like Andy Warhol, may be on to something. As a comment on the social utility of some of what passes for advanced legal scholarship, the Outsiders may have it about right.

On the other hand, one might wish to divert some of the energy of Outsiders to the vast and neglected opportunities to bring their humanity and intellect to the conduct of the more obscure public officers who run our cities, counties, school districts, and states, where modest gains in the pursuit of justice might be achieved, albeit without reward in the coin of academic status…

These disjunctions between academic thought about law and the work of courts or legislatures suggest that the legal academy bears little responsibility for the overbearing tendencies of the judiciary remarked in the previous chapters. What we may see are parallel, not sequential, developments within the legal profession. On the other hand, Frankfurter may have been accurate in describing the Supreme Court in its moments of hubris as seekers of the approval of the intellectual avant-garde.

While there were many academic critics of the Warren Court’s tendency to overreach its commission, their number diminished as those who remem- bered the 1930s were replaced by those who were attracted to law by their youthful hope to participate in broad social reform through constitutional litigation in federal courts. Those academicians who speculate as would-be Platonic Guardians are disposed to prefer that the Republic’s judges sit on a woolsack of discretion such as that of the feudal Court of Chancery and to applaud those who presume to do justice according to a ruling conscience or natural law that is at best the presumed wisdom of a ruling class.

For this reason, a vast amount of academic energy has been invested in the task of reconciling the constitutional role of the judiciary with democracy. Most of what can be usefully said on that subject was said at the time of ratification. For judges such as Cooley and Brandeis, the task of reconciliation was not especially difficult: Their view was that democratic legislation is valid unless explicitly proscribed by the text of a constitution ratified by the people and subject to modification by them; judicial review in their view is avowedly anti-democratic and should therefore be practiced with restraint assuring the moral and political primacy of legislation. However, the task of reconciliation becomes difficult and worthy of heroic intellectual efforts when thinking proceeds from the contrary premise that restraint should not be practiced and judges should be encouraged to enforce not only the text of constitutions, but also principles of natural law developed by academic discourse in political and moral philosophy.

Thus, an extensive academic literature argues that judicial review should be ever more intensive because of the deficiencies inherent in democratic legislation. Legislatures, it is said, are chiefly known as places in which we express our selfish impulses, an observation it would be difficult to contest. Because venal interest groups influence legislation, it is reasoned, government by decree emanating from the life-tenured elite is theoretically superior to democratic self-government. Others have striven to justify the overbearing conduct of the Supreme Court as a fulfillment of eighteenth-century republican expectations; these arguments tend to rest on the alleged congruence of the substance of the Court’s agenda with the politics of some founders. In essence, it has been suggested, the Court is somehow the real voice of the people, much as the king’s chancellor was the real voice of the Crown. Justice Brennan himself apparently deemed his principles to have the sanction of democratic self-government so long as the self-governing citizens accepted them, that is, did not rebel against his decisions. While he acknowledged the law he created and administered to be the product of his generation’s “experience and understanding, its passion and reason,” he was apparently untroubled that his passions were the product of his own experience and were not widely shared except among a limited professional class. Theories in this vein have been multiplied by academic authors, but a common theme has been that the Court should be more attentive to the advice of the moral philosophers of the academy and less attentive to “the common thoughts of men.”

Despite the enumerated limitations and overconfidence of legal academic theorists, their work has a synergistic effect. Academic theorists do, as Frankfurter observed, provide a receptive, sometimes even a fawning, audi- ence for heroic judges and give less frequent applause to text-bound legal doctrines. Justice Brennan, for example, could seemingly do no wrong. Even his extraordinary dissent in Michael H. v. Gerald D. received uncritical acceptance among theoreticians. Ronald Dworkin, Frank Michelman, and Kathleen Sullivan celebrated it as an exemplary “moral reading” of the Constitution, without expression of serious concern that such a moral read- ing is a finger in the eye of self-government.

While most theoreticians will on occasion acknowledge that not all morally correct opinions are also law, Judge Posner is not wrong to observe a tendency to conflation. That conflation is the risk feared by Brandeis when he questioned the teaching of philosophy. It tends to be a reason for the occasional attractions of academic moral philosophy to judges and the lawyers who appear before them. They, for the reasons stated by Mill, tend to be attracted to ideas empowering themselves. If the Holmesian lightning bolt of genius is that courts ought to be less constrained and more aggressive in the exercise of their powers, many judges and lawyers will experience a self-inflationary gratification from the message. A dramatic example of academic theory that may be taken too seriously by judges and lawyers is the discovery by academicians of international human rights law as a category of our national law…

These scholars reveal customary international law as yet another form of unenacted natural law to be enforced by life-tenured judges. That law is based on what judges call concern about current international conventions not ratified by the United States, or conceptions of justice in other countries around the world, about which the primary sources of information are the academic authors who urge its enforcement. For example, the South African Constitutional Court in 1995 was induced to decide the constitutionality of capital punishment substantially on the basis of international precedents; this is presented as a model for a global system to be enforced in the United States by the federal judiciary.

In early times, the federal courts were charged to enforce the law of admiralty having its origins in international practice and understanding and to customary law governing the relations between nations, such as the law of diplomatic immunity. In recent years, lower federal courts have in addition asserted jurisdiction to enforce customary international law of other sorts. The American Law Institute has now lent its support to the idea that customary international law, as discerned by the federal judiciary, is federal law, perhaps superseding even prior federal legislation. While not long ago it was possible to suppose that customary international human rights law was narrowly limited to such matters as genocide and torture, we are now told that the list is not closed and has, due to improved communications around the globe, grown to include gender discrimination, religious rights, rights relating to sexual orientation, and the right to be free from “hate speech.”

We are also told by contemporary Langdells that life-tenured judges “find,” and do not “make,” such customary international law, and we are assured that, also among the rights to be protected, is the right to live in a democratic society. The irony of this last assurance seems to be invisible to those who give it, nor does it dissuade life-tenured federal judges from repairing to Colorado in the summertime to attend seminars on customary international human rights law conducted by experts in that field. Or constrain other efforts to persuade the judiciary that they are members of “a global community” and that an international outlook on moral issues is more appropriate than obedience to the conventionalities of insensitive American habitats. When it was observed that the expansion of customary international law to include unenacted laws regarding “human rights” threatens to effect a vast displacement of state law made by judges and legislators who are accountable to the people they serve, Harold Koh responded by expressing disdain for state and local law, and for the right to self-government. For him, any matter having even secondary international effects is an appropriate subject for federalization pursuant to the foreign affairs powers of the federal government. If the federal courts have long decided the scope of diplomatic immunity, then it is in this view but a modest step for them to decide whether capital punishment violates an international norm. Nor should it matter that the United States has refused to ratify a particular convention, or has ratified it only subject to conditions precluding its appli- cation to displace state law. Koh seems to hope that if the life-tenured federal judiciary were not to impose as customary international law of their own devising (reflecting the presumably elevated morality of human rights scholars), American states might practice genocide on their citizens.

There was for a time a substantial evangelical campaign to transfer American legal traditions to developing countries. That campaign was aborted when its champions recognized that the economic and social infrastructure of the receiving nations is so different with respect to such matters as class and tribal rivalries that the American experience was simply inap- plicable. It is for the same reason nonsense to suppose that the issue of capital punishment, much less that of “hate speech,” can be universalized. It is amply difficult for American judges to resolve such issues in the context of an American culture of which they have at least some knowledge; to involve them in the administration of natural law principles derived from the whole of human experience is a form of cultural imperialism. It is also an invitation to judicial arrogance desensitizing the American legal profession to its responsibility for our own democratic institutions.

What is frequently lacking in much academic legal discourse is attention to those aspects of legal institutions that generate the loyalty of the citizens expected to sustain them by their obedience. As Burke said, “[I]n the groves of their academy, at the end of every vista, you see nothing but gallows. Nothing is left which engages the affections on the part of the commonwealth.” Rarely is recognition given in academic literature to the role of law as a confirmation of conventional morality and as a message of reason- able to the good citizens who do the Republic’s work that it is indeed their Republic.

While there is thus a synergy between these phenomena, the inter-relationships between heroic judging and theoretical scholarship are likely minor effects. As Lieber (who learned it from Savigny) and his adherents would have been quick to affirm, both developments are surely driven by larger forces operating within the legal profession and derived from the larger culture of which they are a part. Judges and professors, as well as many lawyers, are members of Wiebe’s “national class.” Their thoughts are the product of an industrial era, an age that believed all things possible, and even the remaking of a self-governing society into a utopia “void of crime and poverty” by technical experts on the bench. And they are also the product of a time when the Republic came to fill the role of a global empire threatened by an evil adversary that…personified mob rule. …It is the imperial America that has made the legal profession what it is at the end of the twentieth century, not the legal profession that made America.

Justice Byron White served as contrarian to the Supreme Court in the heroic age of Justice Brennan.

Posted in Law | Comments Off on Stewards Of Democracy: Law As Public Profession (1999)

Why Is The Elite Media Singing From The Same Hymnal About The Trump-Putin Summit? (8-17-25)

01:00 Why Do Elite News Operations Sound So Dumb So Often? https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162886
13:00 Industrial Policy’s Potential with Marc Fasteau and Ian Fletcher, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=MykCxs4aFl4
21:00 Yoram Hazony: The Man Driving the Nationalist Revival on the Right, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162566
1:08:00 Industrial Policy for the United States: Winning the Competition for Good Jobs and High-Value Industries (2025), https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162358
1:17:00 Attitudes to AI are a rorschach’s test
1:34:00 Megyn Kelly on Russiagate and the New York Times, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162867
1:40:00 The Prestige Economy, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162904
1:50:00 The Engineered Chinese State Vs Lawyerly America, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162900
1:52:00 Ira Israel: Could Enlightenment Mean Accepting Our Own Insignificance?, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162921
2:03:00 The most powerful systems of epistemic closure in America today, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162850
2:20:00 Russiagate and the New York Times, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162867
2:30:00 The Politics of Expertise, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162857
2:55:00 What Goes Unsaid In Stephen P. Turner’s Autobiography Mad Hazard: A Life in Social Theory?, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162822
3:58:00 Individualism Is Not A Right-Wing Value, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162613
4:01:00 ‘The Making of the American Conservative Mind: National Review and Its Times’ (2005), https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=162696

Grok says:

Luke Ford (aka Fordy) demonstrates a reasonable degree of self-awareness in parts of the transcript, such as when he explicitly acknowledges his own incentives for promoting alternative narratives (e.g., “I have very strong incentives to buy into conspiracy theories… because I just can’t repeat back to you what other people do more effectively”). He also admits to his right-wing hero system and personal background influences (e.g., his upbringing, conversions, and resentment toward “cool kids”). However, there are several areas where he lacks self-awareness, often manifesting as hypocrisy, projection, or failure to apply his own critiques inward. Below, I outline key instances, grouped thematically, with supporting quotes and reasoning. These highlight inconsistencies between his stated principles (e.g., valuing truth over prestige, avoiding groupthink) and his behavior or rhetoric.

1. Hypocrisy in Critiquing Media Groupthink and Prestige Economies Ford repeatedly accuses elite media of “singing from the same hymnal” due to prestige-seeking, incentives for conformity, and epistemic closure (ignoring contrary evidence to protect a “hero system”). Yet, he exhibits similar patterns in his own monologue, echoing dissident-right or alt-media tropes (e.g., lab leak theories, racial realism, critiques of immigration assimilation) without acknowledging how this aligns him with a niche “herd” for his own status in alternative circles. This suggests a blind spot: he sees himself as an outsider truth-teller but doesn’t recognize his content as a mirror of the prestige economy he decries.

Example: He says, “Why is it the people who hold the most prestige frequently say the dumbest things? And it comes to me that often belonging to any group requires a certain amount of singing from the same hymnal… You have to say these stupid things to maintain your standing among the cool kids in the elite news media.”

Lack of self-awareness: Ford positions himself as exempt from this, but his monologue frequently parrots unorthodox views (e.g., “groups do not tend to assimilate in a profound way… Japanese Americans have certain life results that are more similar to the life results of the Japanese in Japan”) that align with right-wing online communities. He doesn’t reflect on how this might be his own “hymnal” for audience capture or personal prestige in dissident spaces, especially as a YouTuber seeking views.

Example: “The prestige economy is not the same as the merit economy… Credibility will largely flow from status, not from telling the truth. You will raise your status, not by telling the truth, generally speaking, but by assimilating to the high status position.”

Lack of self-awareness: Ford critiques this system but builds his show around contrarian takes (e.g., conspiracy-friendly framings of Russia Gate or Biden’s senility) that boost his niche status. He admits incentives for uniqueness but doesn’t probe how his “truth-seeking” might be performative, akin to the media’s “neutrality” facade he mocks.

2. Projection of Epistemic Closure and Hero Systems Onto Others Ford draws on Ernest Becker’s “hero systems” and epistemic closure to explain why people (e.g., media elites) shield themselves from contrary views to maintain meaning and identity. He applies this astutely to others but rarely turns it inward, overlooking how his own right-wing hero system (e.g., nationalism, group interests over individualism) creates similar blinders. This is ironic given his emphasis on self-reflection.

Example: “With every hero system comes a system of epistemic closure… You are shielded from all arguments that can contradict or undermine your hero system… No matter what happens, people almost never change their mind.”

Lack of self-awareness: Ford identifies as a “man of the right” and admits his hero system shifted (e.g., from Protestantism to encountering Dennis Prager and Judaism), but he doesn’t examine how his current views (e.g., skepticism of diversity’s benefits: “The more diverse America becomes… the less Americans have in common”) might involve closure. For instance, he dismisses liberal critiques (e.g., Ezra Klein’s interview style as partisan) without considering if his own framing (e.g., portraying media as uniformly biased against Trump) is equally closed-off to pro-establishment evidence.

Example: “If you get humiliated often enough with your particular hero system… you will start to look for alternatives and then you’ll become open to contrary points of view.”Lack of self-awareness: Ford shares personal humiliations (e.g., resentment toward “cool kids” excluding him for merit/truth pursuits: “It’s normal to feel some resentment… Why don’t I have their status?”) but frames them as making him wiser, not as fueling his own epistemic biases. He doesn’t reflect on how this resentment might drive his anti-elite rants, projecting “humiliation” dynamics onto media without seeing it in himself.

3. Inconsistent Stance on Individualism vs. Group Loyalty Ford critiques individualism as a “left-wing” trait (e.g., incompatible with right-wing values like duty, hierarchy, and group interests), praising collective systems (e.g., nationalism, tribalism). However, his life story and presentation reveal a highly individualistic path—conversions, personal intellectual journeys, and a solo YouTube show—which he doesn’t reconcile with his ideology. This shows a disconnect between his preached values and lived experience.

Example: “Individualism is some key essential right-wing value… And in this new biography of William F. Buckley is repeatedly described as an individualist… But he doesn’t come across as particularly right-wing.”Lack of self-awareness: Ford lambasts Buckley and National Review figures (e.g., Frank Meyer, Russell Kirk) as “individualists” unfit for true conservatism, yet his own narrative is individualistic: e.g., “I moved to America… America has much more veneration of the individual… I formed a right-wing hero system… I read this book… it makes the point…” He describes solitary pursuits (e.g., reading Becker, interviewing academics) without noting the irony that his “right-wing” identity seems self-constructed, not dutifully inherited from a group/tradition.

Example: “Right-wing moral reasoning is not every man for himself… That’s every man in his place in service of the group… Your role is to align yourself with these external standards.”Lack of self-awareness: Ford emphasizes group duty but hosts a show that’s “every man for himself” (solo rants, personal anecdotes like “I have made great progress on many of my dates” without “official pronouncements”). He critiques Protestantism/evangelicalism for individual focus (“rejects traditional… holds fast the literal words of scripture and the power of the individual”) but doesn’t address how his own Protestant upbringing and conversions echo this “left-wing” individualism.

Joke 1: The Hymnal Hypocrisy
“Luke Ford walks into a room and says, ‘Why’s everyone singing from the same media hymnal? Bunch of prestige-chasing sheep!’ Then he grabs his YouTube mic, belts out the alt-right’s greatest hits, and wonders why the room’s chanting, ‘Luke, you’re leading the choir!'”

Joke 2: Hero System Blind Spot
“Luke’s reading Ernest Becker, shouting, ‘Everyone’s trapped in their hero system, shielding themselves from truth!’ Meanwhile, his right-wing hero system’s so strong, it’s got a fortress, a moat, and a ‘No Liberals Allowed’ sign. Self-awareness? Luke says, ‘What’s that, a conspiracy theory?'”

Joke 3: Individualist in Denial
“Luke says, ‘Right-wingers love duty, not individualism—that’s left-wing nonsense!’ Then he spends four hours monologuing solo on YouTube about his personal journey from Australia to Prager to Judaism. Luke, buddy, you’re so individualistic, you’re basically a one-man tribe!”

Joke 4: Dating Anecdote Disaster
“Luke goes, ‘I made great progress on my dates, no official pronouncements needed!’ Then he wonders why his dates ghost him when he starts lecturing about epistemic closure mid-dinner. Luke, maybe they just didn’t want to join your hero system!”

ChatGPT:

1. Media groupthink vs. your own hymnal

“The cool kids have to say dumb things to stay in their group. Me? I just say dumb things on YouTube for free.”

2. Prestige economy hypocrisy

“I rail against the prestige economy… then brag about my $186 Financial Times subscription like it’s a Rolex.”

“I said credibility comes from status, not truth. Which is why I keep quoting Ernest Becker like he’s my Costco card.”

3. Hero systems projection

“I explain how nobody ever changes their hero system. Then I tell you about how I changed mine five times before breakfast.”

“I say resentment drives elite media… while I’m still mad the cool kids didn’t let me sit at their lunch table in 1984.”

4. Individualism vs. collectivism

“I preach that the right is about duty to the group, not individualism. Then I fire up my solo livestream and rant for three hours about my dates.”

“Nothing says ‘group loyalty’ like moving countries, changing religions twice, and starting your own YouTube channel.”

5. Dating ‘progress’ metaphor

“I said just because the media doesn’t announce progress doesn’t mean it didn’t happen. Just like my dates. Sure, there’s no press release—but trust me, history was made.”

“The Pentagon should issue my dating life as an official statement: vague, no measurable progress, but technically still ongoing.”

Gemini:

On projecting his own biases onto others:

“He says everyone has a ‘hero system’ that creates blind spots, but then he goes on a rant about how his own hero system makes him ‘wiser.’ That’s like a fish giving a lecture on the dangers of water”.

“He uses his resentment toward the ‘cool kids’ to explain why the media is bad, but he doesn’t realize he’s just auditioning for a new cool kids club”.

On being an individualist while advocating for group loyalty:

“He criticizes individualism and praises group loyalty, which is an interesting take for a guy with a solo show named after himself”.

“He says he’s a ‘man of the right,’ but his life story is the most individualistic thing you could imagine: leaving one religion, finding another, and starting his own intellectual journey on YouTube. He’s a one-man group.”

Posted in America | Comments Off on Why Is The Elite Media Singing From The Same Hymnal About The Trump-Putin Summit? (8-17-25)

Ira Israel: Could Enlightenment Mean Accepting Our Own Insignificance?

I’ve spent my life chasing distinction instead of connection. When I change this habit and spend more energy on connection instead of attention, I not only increase my happiness, I also become more effective.

We can’t always win in the attention economy but we can all become more effective.

What annoys me about pundits is that they primarily promote themselves rather than the truth.

The truth is that we and they are insignificant (except to a tiny number of people connected to us such as family and friends).

If I died today, a dozen people would be devastated and a few hundred people would be sad.

Ira Israel is on to something here:

It may sound paradoxical but what if the path to enlightenment begins with accepting our own insignificance? What if the drive to be “somebody” is what fuels our anxiety and depression?

As a therapist, I often see patients struggling under the weight of needing to feel significant. In helping them, I have found surprising common ground between three different traditions: the Buddhist concept of sunyata, philosopher Jean‑Paul Sartre’s idea of nothingness, and psychoanalyst Jacques Lacan’s notion of subjective destitution. Each challenges our attachment to self‑importance, not to erase the self but to free it. And far from espousing nihilism, each theory outlines a path towards freedom and authenticity.

We live in a culture that rewards visibility — likes, follows, and polished personal “brands” that we create mostly for social media. Most of us are conditioned to equate attention with worth, but this hunger for admiration often breeds alienation, resentment, frustration, jealousy, and disappointment — from others, and even from ourselves. What if well‑being doesn’t come from building shinier facades, but from loosening our holds on trying to be significant?

…The self is not fixed or permanent.

Emptiness or lack is not a defect; it’s the starting point for freedom.

Clinging to self‑importance fuels suffering and alienation.

Letting go invites more responsible, authentic engagement with life.

Rejecting self‑importance doesn’t mean drifting into passivity or cynicism. These ideas can help us redirect our energy toward genuine connection and contribution:

Serve compassionately: Let meaning come from helping others, not from seeking validation.

Live your values quietly: Integrity matters more than applause.

Build inclusive communities: Welcome people for who they are, not what they achieve.

Support larger causes: Invest in the well‑being of the planet and others.

Mentor without ownership: Share knowledge freely, without needing credit.

Create as an offering: Let art or innovation enrich life, not your résumé.

Listen deeply: Hear others without rushing to center yourself.

Be present: Release preoccupation with recognition; focus on the moment at hand.

Practice spontaneous kindness: Give without calculation.

Stay vulnerable: Honest sharing fosters real connection.

Posted in Pundits | Comments Off on Ira Israel: Could Enlightenment Mean Accepting Our Own Insignificance?

The Prestige Economy

The more prestigious your job (such as an Ivy League professor or network news anchor), the more vulnerable you are to cancellation for crime think.

The professor and the elite journalist primarily work in a prestige economy while the businessman and the athlete typically work in a merit economy.

How many economies are there and which ones dominate your life?

ChatGPT: 1. Prestige economy (status-based)

What matters: recognition, reputation, who praises you, where you’re published, who you’re seen with.

Domains: academia, journalism, arts, fashion, politics, social media.

Logic: value is conferred by peers or gatekeepers. You succeed by being recognized as “important,” not necessarily by measurable output.

Downside: herd effects, echo chambers, fear of deviating from consensus.

2. Merit economy (performance-based)

What matters: measurable outcomes, skill, output, or results.

Domains: engineering, some parts of business, sports, surgery.

Logic: value comes from demonstrated ability or productivity — you win the race, you design the bridge that stands.

Downside: merit measures can get gamed; not all “merit” is measurable.

3. Money economy (market-based)

What matters: purchasing power, price signals, capital.

Domains: commerce, labor markets, investment.

Logic: value is set by supply and demand; anyone who can pay can access.

Downside: inequalities compound, wealth isn’t always aligned with wisdom or talent.

4. Bureaucratic economy (rule-based)

What matters: compliance, seniority, credentials, ticking the right boxes.

Domains: government, big corporations, military, HR departments.

Logic: you advance by following the rules, meeting formal criteria, or lasting long enough in the hierarchy.

Downside: sclerosis, box-ticking over substance.

5. Moral economy (norm-based)

What matters: virtue, altruism, adherence to shared values.

Domains: religion, activism, community life.

Logic: esteem and trust are granted for being “good” or “selfless.”

Downside: moral signaling can substitute for effectiveness; purity spirals.

6. Attention economy (visibility-based)

What matters: eyeballs, clicks, followers, virality.

Domains: social media, entertainment, politics.

Logic: value flows to whoever can grab and hold attention, regardless of truth or depth.

Downside: incentivizes outrage, spectacle, simplicity over nuance.

In real life, these overlap. A professor is judged partly on merit (quality of research), partly on prestige (journal placement, who cites them), partly on bureaucracy (tenure rules), and increasingly on attention (social media presence).

Legend: ★★★★★ = dominant, ★☆☆☆☆ = weak

This lets you see at a glance:

Academia = prestige + bureaucracy.

Media = attention + prestige.

Government = bureaucracy + prestige.

Business = money + merit.

Sports = pure merit, but layered with money and attention.

Religion/activism = moral + attention economies.

Tech/engineering = merit + money, though prestige is creeping in (e.g. conference buzz, VC signaling).

How Economies Interact and Distort Each Other

Prestige vs Merit

  • Distortion: Prestige can overshadow real ability. A Harvard degree may be valued more than raw skill.
  • Example: In academia, citation counts and institutional prestige often count more than the actual content of research.

Prestige vs Money

  • Distortion: Money can buy prestige (endowed chairs, naming rights) while prestige can inflate financial value (celebrity endorsements).
  • Example: Universities admit big donors’ kids regardless of academic merit.

Merit vs Bureaucracy

  • Distortion: Bureaucratic rules can block recognition of actual talent, while “meritocratic exams” can be gamed.
  • Example: In government jobs, civil service rules sometimes promote time-in-grade over performance.

Attention vs Merit

  • Distortion: Viral fame can eclipse actual competence.
  • Example: Influencers with millions of followers get lucrative deals while more talented but unknown creators get ignored.

Moral vs Money

  • Distortion: Moral appeals can be monetized, turning causes into brands. Conversely, financial backers shape which causes gain traction.
  • Example: “Green” or “woke” consumerism where virtue is sold as a premium lifestyle choice.

Prestige vs Attention

  • Distortion: High-prestige actors chase attention, diluting their credibility; attention-seekers borrow prestige through association.
  • Example: Scientists on Twitter simplify or exaggerate findings to gain followers, which can undermine long-term trust.

Key Takeaway

Most domains run on a mix of these economies. But when one dominates—especially attention or money—it tends to distort the others. That’s why elite media, academia, and politics so often sound uniform: they are trapped in overlapping prestige–attention–bureaucracy loops that leave little room for pure merit or truth-seeking.
Prestige Economies in Action

Prestige Economies Driving Elite Media Behavior

Biden’s Cognitive Decline Denial

  • Prestige Economy: Elite outlets like NYT and Washington Post prize their credibility and elite standing. Admitting Biden’s decline early would risk sounding like right-wing talking points, which would lower their standing in the prestige hierarchy of journalism.
  • Attention Economy: Stories affirming Biden’s competence were rewarded with clicks from their loyal base, while dissenting voices risked alienating that audience.
  • Bureaucratic Economy: Newsrooms have internal norms—editors, standards desks—that function like bureaucracies. Deviating from the “he’s fine” line meant career risk inside the institution.
  • Result: Groupthink. A uniform narrative of “Biden is sharp” prevailed until obvious signs made denial impossible (Politico eventually broke ranks).

Trump’s Trade Policy Derision

  • Prestige Economy: Economists in places like the Brookings Institution and CBO had long treated free trade as settled orthodoxy. Journalists mirrored that prestige consensus rather than re-examining assumptions.
  • Merit Economy: Actual outcomes (tariff revenue, renegotiated trade deals, resilience arguments) were ignored because they conflicted with the prestige line.
  • Attention Economy: “Trump the fool on trade” stories drove traffic, fitting reader expectations. Nuanced analysis (“tariffs could raise $3 trillion in revenue over a decade” – CBO) was buried.
  • Result: Uniform ridicule—until later, when outcomes complicated the narrative and some humility began creeping in (FT analysis).

Takeaway

Neither case is about truth alone. The uniformity comes from overlapping economies: prestige (status within the profession), attention (traffic and audience loyalty), and bureaucracy (institutional norms). When those dominate, reality gets filtered until it can no longer be ignored.

Russiagate: How the Prestige Economy Produced a Single Story

Economy at workWhat it looked like in coverageReceipts
ClosureEarly boundary-setting: skepticism about “collusion” framed as unserious or partisan; dissenters treated as outside the pale. Mueller Report (redacted, WaPo annotated) (no established conspiracy);
DOJ IG FISA review (17 significant errors/omissions);
Durham Report (2023) (procedural/analytic failures);
2018 Pulitzer to NYT/WaPo for Russia-coverage.
PrestigeHigh-status outlets and security-state alumni defined the respectable view; others echoed to signal professionalism. Pulitzer Board award announcement (2018);
Board later stood by the award (2022).
Anti-neutralityNeutral, wait-and-see reporting often read as “carrying water.” Safe moral stance: assume the worst about Trump/Putin links. Mueller Vol. I (DOJ) on interference vs. conspiracy findings;
Horowitz press PDF (Dec 2019) summarizing FISA problems.
BureaucracyNewsroom norms and sourcing pipelines (intel, DOJ, FBI alumni) rewarded sticking to the herd; editors risk-averse to contrarian frames. House Intel letter on IG findings (details errors/omissions);
House hearing on Durham (2023) (competing interpretations).
AttentionIncentives favored dramatic “Watergate-scale” arcs; reversals or nuance underperformed compared with scandal-forward framing. Mueller report archive (public interest spikes);
Media debate over revoking awards: Axios (2019).

Turner-style takeaway

  • Closure came first (declare the narrative settled), then prestige enforced it (who is credible to say what), while bureaucratic newsroom habits and the attention economy kept the arc intact.
  • When later documents complicated the original frame (Mueller non-establishment of conspiracy; IG FISA errors; Durham’s criticisms), the system largely reframed rather than retracted—preserving credibility capital.

Quick links (primary docs)

In the positivist picture, life (especially intellectual life) runs like a merit economy: each discovery is a brick in the wall of cumulative knowledge, neat and impersonal. That’s what people like Comte or logical positivists hoped for — knowledge as an ever-growing model that nobody can really dispute once the facts are in.

But in practice, as Turner emphasizes, much of life — not just science but culture, politics, journalism — runs like a prestige economy. Knowledge isn’t simply added up; it’s negotiated, policed, and stabilized by people who hold authority, credibility, or symbolic capital. The “conversations” decide what counts as knowledge and what doesn’t.

So how much of life operates like this?

Academia: Almost entirely. Journals, tenure committees, funding agencies, and disciplinary boundaries decide what is knowledge. Prestige hierarchies matter more than raw merit.

Media and public discourse: Heavily. A story is not true or false in the abstract; it’s “true” if The New York Times or The Washington Post says so, and untrue if it comes from “fringe” or “conspiracy” outlets.

Law and politics: Same. Courts and legislative bodies are “conversation arenas” where closure happens not because the facts are final, but because a ruling or statute gives a definition the force of authority.

Everyday life: Even at a smaller scale, reputations and cliques determine who is believed in a workplace, a family, or a church.

Where does the merit economy still operate?

In narrow technical domains where feedback from reality is brutal and immediate — like engineering, surgery, or competitive sports. If the bridge collapses, no amount of prestige talk can save you.

Even then, prestige can shape who gets to build the bridge in the first place, or whose failure gets excused.

So the blunt answer: most of life is prestige economy, with pockets of merit economy wherever the world forces brutal feedback.

Posted in Economics | Comments Off on The Prestige Economy

The Engineered Chinese State Vs Lawyerly America

The Financial Times writes: “China is run as an engineering state that excels at construction while the US has become a lawyerly society that favours obstruction. By 2020 all nine members of the Chinese Politburo’s standing committee had trained as engineers. By contrast, the US has turned into a “government of the lawyers, by the lawyers and for the lawyers.””

Amazon says about this new book, Breakneck: China’s Quest to Engineer the Future:

A riveting, firsthand investigation of China’s seismic progress, its human costs, and what it means for America.

For close to a decade, technology analyst Dan Wang―“a gifted observer of contemporary China” (Ross Douthat)―has been living through the country’s astonishing, messy progress. China’s towering bridges, gleaming railways, and sprawling factories have improved economic outcomes in record time. But rapid change has also sent ripples of pain throughout the society. This reality―political repression and astonishing growth―is not a paradox, but rather a feature of China’s engineering mindset.

In Breakneck, Wang blends political, economic, and philosophical analysis with reportage to reveal a provocative new framework for understanding China―one that helps us see America more clearly, too. While China is an engineering state, relentlessly pursuing megaprojects, the United States has stalled. America has transformed into a lawyerly society, reflexively blocking everything, good and bad

Blending razor-sharp analysis with immersive storytelling, Wang offers a gripping portrait of a nation in flux. Breakneck traverses metropolises like Shanghai, Chongqing, and Shenzhen, where the engineering state has created not only dazzling infrastructure but also a sense of optimism. The book also exposes the downsides of social engineering, including the surveillance of ethnic minorities, political suppression, and the traumas of the one-child policy and zero-Covid.

In an era of animosity and mistrust, Wang unmasks the shocking similarities between the United States and China. Breakneck reveals how each country points toward a better path for the other: Chinese citizens would be better off if their government could learn to value individual liberties, while Americans would be better off if their government could learn to embrace engineering―and to produce better outcomes for the many, not just the few.

Posted in China | Comments Off on The Engineered Chinese State Vs Lawyerly America