Putin Seems Disrespectful Of Human Rights, Bro (3-1-22)

00:00 The moral lens on the Russian invasion of Ukraine
03:00 Colin Liddell joins, https://affirmativeright.blogspot.com/2022/02/putin-has-lost.html
05:00 Why does the dissident right revere Putin?
07:00 Broad revulsion at Putin
10:00 Putin is not Hitler
12:00 The late life crisis
13:00 The revival of NATO
18:40 The end of Putin?
24:00 Is the invasion the West’s fault?
26:00 Will Europe get serious about meeting its energy needs?
28:45 Putin’s de-nazification invasion
33:00 The Last Utopia: Human Rights in History, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=142846
43:30 Boris Johnson seems more secure as PM
45:00 America First
46:00 Nick Fuentes
48:45 French commentator Eric Zemmour runs for president
50:00 Valérie Pécresse, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Val%C3%A9rie_P%C3%A9cresse
1:05:00 Elliott Blatt joins
1:19:30 The Last Utopia: Human Rights in History speech by Samuel Moyn, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=oqtFJZB27M8
1:24:00 The Oxford Handbook of Carl Schmitt, https://lukeford.net/blog/?p=142828
1:26:00 The Dark World of Megachurches, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=hTfKpAWkgJY
1:47:30 Why we were wrong about Ukraine | Frederick Kagan, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=-wC6VfswJtQ
1:51:00 Princeton experts discuss the Russian invasion of Ukraine, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=xWYHzDDs93A

Posted in Russia | Comments Off on Putin Seems Disrespectful Of Human Rights, Bro (3-1-22)

The Last Utopia: Human Rights in History

Here are some highlights from this 2010 book by Samuel Moyn:

* Historians of human rights approach their subject, in spite of its novelty, the way church historians once approached theirs. They regard the basic cause—much as the church historian treated the Christian religion—as a saving truth, discovered rather than made in history. If a historical phenomenon can be made to seem like an anticipation of human rights, it is interpreted as leading to them in much the way church history famously treated Judaism for so long, as a proto-Christian movement simply confused about its true destiny. Meanwhile, the heroes who are viewed as advancing human rights in the world—much like the church historian’s apostles and saints—are generally treated with uncritical wonderment. Hagiography, for the sake of moral imitation of those who chase the flame, becomes the main genre. And the organizations that finally appear to institutionalize human rights are treated like the early church: a fledgling, but hopefully universal, community of believers struggling for good in a vale of tears. If the cause fails, it is because of evil; if it succeeds, it is not by accident but because the cause is just. These approaches provide the myths that the new movement wants or needs.

They match a public and politically consequential consensus about the sources of human rights. Human rights commonly appear in journalistic commentary and in political speeches as a cause both age-old and obvious. At the latest, both historians and pundits focus on the 1940s as the crucial era of breakthrough and triumph. High profile observers—Michael Ignatieff, for example—see human rights as an old ideal that finally came into its own as a response to the Holocaust, which might be the most universally repeated myth about their origins. In the 1990s, an era of ethnic cleansing in southeastern Europe and beyond during which human rights took on literally millennial appeal in the public discourse of the West, it became common to assume that, ever since their birth in a moment of post-Holocaust wisdom, human rights embedded themselves slowly but steadily in humane consciousness in what amounted to a revolution of moral concern. In a euphoric mood, many people believed that secure moral guidance, born out of shock about the Holocaust and nearly incontestable in its premises, was on the verge of displacing interest and power as the foundation of international society. All this fails to register that, without the transformative impact of events in the 1970s, human rights would not have become today’s utopia, and there would be no movement around it.

* The best general explanation for the origins of this social movement and common discourse around rights remains the collapse of other, prior utopias, both state-based and internationalist. These were belief systems that promised a free way of life, but led into bloody morass, or offered emancipation from empire and capital, but suddenly came to seem like dark tragedies rather than bright hopes. In this atmosphere, an internationalism revolving around individual rights surged, and it did so because it was defined as a pure alternative in an age of ideological betrayal and political collapse. It was then that the phrase “human rights” entered common parlance in the English language.

* To give up church history is not to celebrate a black mass instead.

* there is a clear and fundamental difference between earlier rights, all predicated on belonging to a political community, and eventual “human rights.”

* If the state was necessary to create a politics of rights, many nineteenth-century observers wondered, could they have any other real source than its own authority and any other basis than its local meanings?

* what happened for human rights to seem like the only viable kind of universalism there is now.

* “Who will dare to avow that his heart was not lifted up,” Johann Wolfgang von Goethe exclaimed in 1797, “when the new sun first rose in its splendor; when we heard of the rights of man, of inspiring liberty, and of universal equality!” Unlike later human rights, however, they were deeply bound up with the construction, through revolution if necessary, of state and nation. It is now the order of the day to transcend that state forum for rights, but until recently the state was their essential crucible.

* [The human rights crusade emerged out of] “the distrust of utopia together with the desire to have one anyway.”

* Amnesty International’s origins in Christian responses to the Cold War had been unpromising, however, and its slow transformation into a celebrated human rights organization makes clear the necessity of distinguishing among the creation, evolution, and reception of such groups. Thanks to its founder Peter Benenson, AI emerged through an interesting and productive improvisation on earlier Christian peace movements. Together with Eric Baker, a Quaker, Benenson intended to provide a new outlet for idealists disappointed by Cold War stalemate, and especially after socialism had been revealed as a failed experiment. After AI’s inaugural May 28, 1961 Observer spread, “The Forgotten Prisoners,” Benenson recorded that “[t]he underlying purpose of this campaign—which I hope those who are closely connected with it will remember, but never publish—is to find a common base upon which the idealists of the world can co-operate. It is designed in particular to absorb the latent enthusiasm of great numbers of such idealists who have, since the eclipse of Socialism, become increasingly frustrated; similarly it is
geared to appeal to the young searching for an ideal. . .” Quite strikingly, in private Benenson went so far as to conclude that the outlet AI would provide to idealists made its effects on victims unimportant: “It matters more to harness the enthusiasm of the helpers. . . The real martyrs prefer to suffer, and, as I would add, the real saints are no worse off in prison than anywhere on this earth.”

* Whether or not such activism made a difference on the ground, or in the larger process of constructing international norms, it succeeded first of all in giving meaning (as Benenson once hoped) to engaged lives. It was engagement of a sort whose minimalism was its enabling condition and source of power when other post-1968 alternatives were dying. Though she would go on to help found Helsinki (later Human Rights) Watch as the decade closed, Jeri Laber recalled that in the early 1970s she had never heard the phrase “human rights.” Trained in Russian studies, it was not Soviet activism that hooked her but a searing December 1973 New Republic essay written by AI activist Rose Styron on the renaissance of torture around the world. It led Laber to “do something about it.” Having been a parttime food writer for the New York Times shortly before, Laber placed an op-ed piece in that newspaper based on AI information—the first published—within a year of joining the Riverside Amnesty chapter. “I had found a successful formula,” she noted in a memoir. “I began with a detailed description of a horrible form of torture, then explained where it was happening and the political context in which it occurred; I ended with a plea to show the offending government that the world was watching.”

* why are this concept and this movement the ones with which many people affiliated at the time and have affiliated since? If human rights have made any historical difference, it was first in their competitive survival as a motivating ideology in the confusing tumult of 1970s social movements, as they became bound up with the widespread desire to drop utopia and have one anyway. And their substitution of plausible morality for failed politics may have come at a price.

* Today it seems self-evident that among the major purposes— and perhaps the essential point—of international law is to protect individual human rights. “At the start of the new century,” one observer writes, “international law, at least for many theorists and practitioners, has been reconceived. No longer the law of nations, it is the law of human rights.”1 If that transformation is one of the most striking there is in modern law and legal thought, it is even more surprising that it really began only yesterday. Not only did the prehistory of international law through World War II provide no grounds for this development; for decades after, there would have been no way to believe or even to guess that human rights might become the touchstones they are today. Neither drawing from the humane spirit of founders centuries ago nor the recoil to World War II’s atrocities, human rights for international lawyers too are rooted in a startling and recent departure.

* one of the most fascinating testaments to the breakthrough of “human rights” in the late 1970s is the response of philosophers, who after a moment of confusion about their novelty assimilated them to natural rights principles that were themselves being revived.

Posted in Ethics, Human Rights | Comments Off on The Last Utopia: Human Rights in History

What Is The Role Of The State?

From the 2019 book, The Oxford Handbook of Carl Schmitt:

* Oakeshott concedes that authority is seldom durable, no matter the form of political organization achieved. Anarchy always lurks “just below the surface,” and once authority is questioned or denied, civil war becomes a real possibility (1990, 190). Because of a feared “disintegration of the association and the self- alienation of its components,” there “have always been people . . . who have wanted the state to be an integrated community set
on a common course and pursuing a common purpose” (188). Carl Schmitt is one of those people in whom the threat of resurgent disorder occasions the desire for a more substantial source of authority. For him, authority is the source, not the result, of law, because in the end, law cannot protect itself or the association it governs. The consequences of World War I certainly heightened Schmitt’s fears. Germany— with restricted sovereignty, relieved of chunks of its territory, deprived of an effective military, occupied (the Rhineland, and then the Ruhr), denied membership in the promised land of the League of Nations (until 1926), stripped of its merchant fleet, under foreign economic supervision (reparations), and fighting border wars in the east as well as insurrectionary battles not “just below the surface” but on the streets of its major cities— was faced with basic questions of political order and survival. To assume that the “self- authenticating property of respublica”— especially in liberal form, with its postulated autonomy of the individual equipped with prepolitical rights and consumer desires— would be sufficient to hold a political association together was a luxury, Schmitt felt, that Germany could ill afford. A more substantial source of authority (of legitimacy, to use Schmitt’s language) was needed, and during the 1920s and early 1930s Schmitt increasingly found that source to be “the people,” a collected political body (not simply a collection of bodies) with felt obligations to “the nation.” The authority of respublica was to be located not in law but in the popular constituent power that animated the law.

On the other side of the Atlantic, the situation was quite different. The United States had become the globe’s preeminent power. Domestically, however, the country had been traumatized. If the war’s aftermath had inspired Schmitt’s most brilliant dissections of liberal individualism and (moral and economic) deceit, in the United States the opposite occurred. The governmentally organized surveillance, violence, and vigilantism during
Woodrow Wilson’s disastrous second term (1917– 1921) sparked an American liberal rights revolution.2 At the conclusion of his fine study on World War I and the making of modern American citizenship, Christopher Capozzola muses about the relative merits of obligation and rights. “These days,” he writes, “some Americans wish for obligations, hoping to renew among Americans a sense of commitment toward our fellow citizens. Ninety years, they tell us, have put rights, and not obligations, at the center of our political life. Individualism has corroded our common culture and our civic associations; we even bowl alone” (Capozzola 2008, 213). The complaint resonates with us, he admits.

“From such a perspective, the sense of voluntarism and obligation in the political culture of early twentieth- century America must astound” (213). But, he insists, the humiliation, persecution, imprisonment, and murder of German Americans and other immigrants; the stepped- up terror waged against African Americans; the flare- up of antisemitism; the violation of religious conscience; and the violent destruction of the radical labor movement
and the Socialist Party tell a different story. “Those who seek something beyond the rights revolution must understand the political culture that existed before rights talk, when obligation still held sway. In a divided and unequal society, civil society could be an arena for negotiating political obligation; it could also be a weapon wielded against the weak” (214). Capozzola’s is a necessary reminder and warning, not least because his example is not taken from one of the usual totalitarian suspects. The coupling of civil society and the state can be brutal, even in liberal democracies. But, alas, rights themselves are no magic shield. Beyond their negative, fragmentary consequences, ones that turn citizens into consumers and politics into slogans about the oikos (“Are you better off today than you were four years ago?”— “It’s the economy, stupid!”), rights frequently not only fail to protect individuals and groups (African Americans, Japanese Americans, Muslim Americans), but can also become weapons (the right to private property, for instance) wielded against the weak.3 Most alarming, however, at least to Schmitt, is the sense that a reliance on rights (civil, human, or other) threatens to enfeeble popular political will, thereby replacing political decision with legal, bureaucratic procedure. And indeed, in
the world in which we now live, “human rights” trump self- determination (Moyn 2010).

Reading Carl Schmitt becomes an exercise in contemplating contradictions: the public versus the private, duties versus rights, collective equality versus individual liberty.

* Italian political theorist Norberto Bobbio firmly insisted that modern democracy is necessarily formal and procedural. “I have stated on other occasions,” he wrote in the mid- 1980s, “and I will never tire of repeating
it, that it is impossible to ever understand anything about democracy until it is realized that a democratic system nowadays signifies first and foremost a set of procedural rules, among which majority rule is the main, but not the only one” (Bobbio 1987, 63). Perhaps “nowadays” is the key word in that proclamation, because Bobbio is keenly aware of the history of an antagonism between the ideal of democracy based on a “social” or “substantial”
notion of equality and liberalism as a political movement that emerged at the beginning of the nineteenth century in opposition to both the monarchical principle and popular sovereignty. Individual liberty, formal equality before the law, and constitutional government (understood primarily as the separation of powers and guarantee
of select subjective rights) were advanced to combat the absolutist “tyrant” as well as the “tyranny of the mob.”

* The battle between liberalism and democracy is the battle between the hegemony of liberty over equality, on the one hand, and equality over liberty, on the other. According to Bobbio, “liberty and equality are antithetical values, in the sense that neither can be fully realized except at the expense of the other: a liberal laissez- faire society is inevitably inegalitarian, and an egalitarian society is inevitably illiberal” (1990, 32). To fuse
the two political ideologies, one needs to tweak definitions, primarily by weakening the meaning of equality. “There is only one form of equality— equality in the right to liberty—which is not only compatible with liberalism but equally demanded by its view of freedom” (33). Thus, “nowadays” democracy must restrict its desire for equality to the aforementioned liberal ideals of equality before the law and equal rights. A problem that this hybrid creature called liberal democracy cannot examine is the fact that just because one has a right to equality does not mean that one necessarily has the material means to enjoy its concrete exercise. Liberalism habitually brushes this inconvenient detail aside and thereby wins its battle with democracy, for whereas liberal ideals seemingly need no alteration, older, “substantial” definitions of democracy are discredited or simply disappear. Modern liberal- democracy in its “juridical- institutional” sense is “procedural,” in that it emphasizes a “body of rules,” Bobbio maintains; it is a formal “government by the people.” What liberal democracy supplants is an “ethical” vision that promotes “substantial” equality not only of opportunity but also of achievement and therefore exerts itself to be a “government for the people” (31– 32; emphasis added).

This latter, older version, Bobbio says, is to be rejected, for “today non- democratic liberal states would be inconceivable, as would non- liberal democratic states” (38). Like “nowadays” above, “today” here accepts the liberal definition of equality and thus the liberal modification— or mollification— of democracy as an irreversible (and of course desirable) fait accompli. Based on this victory, then, Bobbio can decry Carl Schmitt’s
“withering critiques of democracy” (1987, 122), even though by the late 1920s, especially in his Constitutional Theory (a text Bobbio often cites), Schmitt saw himself as a classic democrat at war with liberalism’s enervating assault on all things political.

* Private pleasures wholly replace political participation, for modernity no longer permits direct, public citizenship. Based on property rights and grown to a size that is unmanageable by communally deliberative methods, the modern state, [Benjamin] Constant says, has happily hit upon the idea of representative government, which removes from the citizen the burdensome necessity of political knowledge and intimate participation. Popular sovereignty, no matter how stridently proclaimed, is at best illusory. “Lost in the multitude,” Constant writes, “the individual can almost never perceive the influence he exercises. Never does his will impress itself upon the whole; nothing confirms in his eyes his own cooperation” (1988, 311). Accordingly, the pleasure afforded the ancients by their exercise of political rights is no longer attainable. Rather, our pleasure is taken privately. Whereas “the aim of the ancients was the sharing of social power among the citizens of the same fatherland,” the “aim of the moderns is the enjoyment of security in private pleasures; and they call liberty the guarantee accorded by institutions to these pleasures” (312). It is almost as if he were singing us lullabies: “The sole aim of the modern nations is repose, and with repose comfort, and, as a source of comfort, industry” (54). The
citizen becomes the bourgeois; the political actor the passive consumer. Hush little baby, don’t you cry. Or rather, and much more to the point, the interests of the political subserve those of the economy. With disarming honesty, Constant exults: “The effects of commerce extend even further: not only does it emancipate individuals, but, by creating credit, it places authority itself in a position of dependence. . . . Power threatens; wealth rewards: one eludes power by deceiving it; to obtain the favours of wealth one must serve it: the latter is
therefore bound to win” (325). Constant leaves us in no doubt whose interests the representatives of representative government represent.

For Carl Schmitt, Benjamin Constant’s lineaments of modernity produce a consumptive portrait of a pale humanity engaged only in passive pleasures, eschewing public responsibility. Throughout his work and often with a fine and elegant pathos, Schmitt knew how to eviscerate this liberal ethos of wealth and property buffed with the patina
of self- assured morality. To say, as does the consistent liberal, that all vice lies on the side of the state and all virtue with civil society is to elide the necessary efficacy of the public— that is to say— of the political altogether.

* For Schmitt, Constant’s views are not unique but rather stand as exemplary of a common eighteenth- and nineteenth-century view. Freedom, progress, and reason in alliance with the economy, industry, and technology are prized and pitted against the evils of feudalism, reaction, force, state, war, and politics. What emerges from this confrontation is the triumph of parliamentarianism (liberalism) over dictatorship (of the monarch or the people; Schmitt 2007a, 75). The result, in other words, is the desired victory of civil society as the repository of all that is good over the state and the sinister machinations of politics.

* The political is a stage upon which actors display the making of decisions and their explicit and implicit consequences. The audience is comprised of spectators or perhaps participant- spectators, depending on the form of political organization prevalent in a given state. Economic activity occurs in the lobby where buying and selling goes on. If actual political decisions are made by the various transactions occurring in the lobby rather than the actions portrayed on the stage, then the audience is deceived as the actors hide the fact that they are mere marionettes manipulated from afar.

* “Democracy requires . . . first homogeneity and second— if the need arises— elimination or eradication of heterogeneity. . . . A democracy demonstrates its political power by knowing how to refuse or keep at bay something foreign and unequal that threatens its homogeneity” (Schmitt 1985, 9). The contemporary reader, who claims definitive knowledge of the moral lessons of twentieth- century history and is convinced of the unshakable
quality of learned norms that are said to be innate human rights, will be chilled by the notion of homogeneity and the seeming brutality of the language of exclusion contained in these two sentences.

* In Schmitt’s world, for “a people” to exist, it must pick the national distinction around which to rally, if for no other reason than that the national distinction is (or has become) the territorial distinction and thus the physically defensible distinction. In a world of nation- states, the nation- state is supreme. To raise another distinction above all others— one’s Christianity, one’s class, one’s “local” territory— would be to incite civil war, which would make the collective vulnerable to forces and pressures coming from the outside. The democratic community, in Schmitt’s view, is forever defined by this threat.

* Basic rights— now commonly called human rights— are generally thought of as prepolitical, and fear of state power and the desire structurally to limit its extent motivates all liberal constitutions. Again, Constant can be our guide. “No authority on earth is unlimited,” he admonishes us, “neither that of the people, nor that of the men who declare themselves their representatives, nor that of the kings, by whatever title they reign, nor, finally, that of the law. . . . The individuals possess individual rights independently of all social and political authority, and any authority which violates these rights becomes illegitimate”… In the liberal world so depicted, the single most important political imperative is to place limits on the political.

* The liberal state, then, has no other function than preserving the rights of the “egoistic” individual pursuing his or her private pleasures, and both K/ Carls, for different reasons, have a problem with that.

* Emmanuel Sieyes: “The nation exists prior to everything; it is the origin of everything. Its will is always legal. It is the law itself. Prior to the nation and above the nation there is only natural law. A nation never leaves the state of nature and, amidst so many perils, it can never have too many possible ways of expressing its will. . . . [A] nation is independent of all forms and, however it may will, it is enough for its will to be made known for all positive law to fall silent in its presence, because it is the source and supreme master of all positive law. . . . A nation should not and cannot subject itself to constitutional forms.”

Posted in Carl Schmitt | Comments Off on What Is The Role Of The State?

Russia Invades Ukraine (2-24-22)

Posted in Russia, Ukraine | Comments Off on Russia Invades Ukraine (2-24-22)

What Does Putin Want? (2-23-22)

00:00 Putin at war (choppy audio first two minutes)
03:00 PROFESSOR JOHN MEARSHEIMER: THE SITUATION IN RUSSIA AND UKRAINE, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Nbj1AR_aAcE
45:00 Ricardo vs Kyle
49:00 Kyle on the importance of alliances
57:30 Is China more likely to invade Taiwan with America distracted?
59:30 Is Putin pursuing his legacy as opposed to Russia’s best interests?
1:13:00 Covid reveals our lack of social cohesion
1:18:00 Do we want to get into a ground war with Putin?
1:23:30 Canadian trucker convoy & Trudeau crackdown
1:24:00 Americans are harder than Canadians, Scandinavians
1:30:00 Kyle on right-wing populism
1:49:00 Deglobalization
1:51:30 Elliott Blatt joins
1:55:00 Democrats hate oil, mining, trucks
2:04:00 How significant was January 6?
2:21:00 Conservative solutions to homelessness
2:35:00 Kyle on the problems with birth control
2:41:20 How Kyle’s thinking has developed
2:49:00 Bayesian reasoning, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Bayesian_inference
2:56:00 Kyle on Peter Thiel and his candidates

Posted in Russia, Ukraine | Comments Off on What Does Putin Want? (2-23-22)